Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
06-01-2002, 03:00 PM | #31 | |
Regular Member
Join Date: May 2002
Location: North America
Posts: 203
|
bd-from-kg:
Thanks for your time. Quote:
You suggest that one sense of the word "can" is "a nonzero probability" that an action will be performed. Consider the author's second formulation of his argument: 1'. We should believe only propositions for which we have adequate justification. Premises 2-7 remain the same and 8 becomes: 8'. I have adequate justification for MFT. It seems as though your sense of "can" would work in premises 2 and 3 and yield the conclusion that if determinism is true then anyone who believes in free will is justified in believing it. Pointing out that there is more than one sense of "can" would only undermine the argument if the author couldn't use the same sense in premises 2 and 3 in the same argument. Consider this famous argument: 1. All men are mortal. 2. Socrates is a man. 3. Therefore Socrates is mortal. If you accept that the term "man" can be used in the same sense in the same argument (as above) then the argument will work. It makes no difference to the argument above that there are different meanings of the word "man" that would yield another argument which has false or improbable premises. So if there are other senses of the word "can" that seems to make little difference. And I see no reason why the author cannot use one sense of "can" in both premises 2 and 3 that would yield premises that are highly plausible. Consider premise 3: If determinism is true in the actual world then there is "a nonzero probability" that some people will believe in free will (since some people obviously do believe in it and the probability of any event in the real world given determinism is 1). Now consider premise 2: It claims that if you think someone "should" or "ought" to do something then you must presuppose that they can do it. The "should" here is "believe only propositions for which we have adequate justification". And the "can" would be "there is a nonzero probability that we will believe only propositions for which we have adequate justification". So we have: 1. We should believe only propositions for which we have adequate justification. 2. Whatever should be done, has a nonzero probability of being done. 3. If determinism is true, then whatever has a nonzero probability of being done, is done. What is objectionable about these premises? Premise 2 seems the one most likely to attract attention. But surely, if I tell you that you SHOULD do something I must presuppose that you CAN do it. Or I must presuppose that there is "a nonzero probability" that you will do it. |
|
06-01-2002, 08:50 PM | #32 | ||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Oct 2000
Location: Alberta, Canada
Posts: 5,658
|
Those premises are attempting to sneak the conclusion in again.
Look at premise two: Quote:
Now, look at premise three: Quote:
Using those premises, presumably you are going to construct something like this: Quote:
So, finally we look at premise one: Quote:
Now, the argument can be taken apart in other ways, such as by accepting the first premise and second premises as using "should" in the conventional sense and combining them. In that case, the third premise will either be unable to be combined or be false. |
||||
06-02-2002, 03:14 AM | #33 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: Canton, Ohio
Posts: 2,082
|
Taffy,
If determinism and free will are polar opposites, as you seem to express them, then one could come up with numerous arguments about their relationship simply because interpretations of either word suggest what the final arugument must be. In opposition, they define each other. Now, if you can see determinism and free will from an evolutionary perpective, since you see these abstractions as somehow a human dilemma, you would find no polarization, no deterministic outcome and no problem defining free will. Ierrellus [ June 02, 2002: Message edited by: Ierrellus ]</p> |
06-02-2002, 09:52 AM | #34 | ||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Taffy Lewis:
By now tronvillain has pretty well demolished this argument, but (since I had almost finished this anyway) here’s my take from a slightly different angle. Quote:
First, to eliminate a possible red herring, the statement “’determinism is true’ implies ‘all beliefs are true’” could well be true if “implies” is used in the sense of standard logical implication. In this sense of “implies”, “A implies B” is true if and only if A is false or B is true. And of course it may well be that “determinism is true” is false. This is often called “weak implication”. But we’re talking here about logical entailment, not weak implication. To say that A entails B is to say that B is true in all possible worlds in which A is true. But obviously there are possible worlds in which determinism is true but not all beliefs are true. Surely you don’t dispute this? So determinism does not entail that all beliefs are true, which means that one of the author’s first three premises is false. End of story. [By the way, the point is not that determinism has self-contradictory consequences, but that the premises entail obviously false propositions. If you’re right in believing that the author understands that his first three premises entail that “‘determinism is true” entails ‘all beliefs are true’” yet still believes that his argument is sound, it’s a waste of time to read anything he writes (unless for entertainment).] To show that the problem here has nothing to do with determinism, let’s dispense with the third premise and consider only the generalized version of the first premise and the second premise. That is: (1) We should always refrain from believing falsehoods. (2) Whatever should be done can be done. Now what is the nature of these premises? In what sense are they being claimed to be true? Clearly they are not meant to be statements about the real world; that is, there are no possible observations that would tend to confirm or falsify them. Thus the only possible interpretation is that the author takes these premises to be necessary truths – statements which are true in all possible worlds. If they are not necessary truths, there is no reason whatever to suppose that they are true at all; in fact, it is impossible to assign them any intelligible meaning except as necessary truths. But now observe that these two premises yield: (3) We can always refrain from believing falsehoods. And this is clearly not a necessary truth: it is not true in all possible worlds. Plainly one can imagine without self-contradiction a world in which there is at least one person who is certain to have at least one false belief. But (3) is rigorously entailed by (1) and (2), and necessary truths entail only necessary truths. So one of the premises is not a necessary truth, which is to say (since it is not a statement about the real world) that it is false or meaningless. Quote:
(3') We can believe only propositions for which we have adequate justification. Once again, this is clearly not a necessary truth: there are obviously possible worlds in which there is zero probability that no one will have any beliefs for which he lacks adequate justification. So one of the premises is not a necessary truth. Etc. Quote:
Quote:
Thus if you are using “should” in a sense that makes your second premise true, the first premise must be modified to read “It is desirable to believe only propositions for which we have adequate justification.” This modification makes the first premise plausible, but it does not allow the argument to go through. In any case, although this is an amusing academic exercise, it is self-evident that if a conclusion about the real world cannot be validly derived from true premises about the real world, it cannot be validly derived by adding moral premises. Thus the entire proof is in the same category as a proof that all triangles are isosceles (or better yet, a proof to this effect using moral premises). It is obvious at the outset that the proof must be fallacious; the interesting question is not whether all triangles are indeed isosceles, but where the fallacy lies. |
||||
06-02-2002, 03:44 PM | #35 | ||
Regular Member
Join Date: May 2002
Location: North America
Posts: 203
|
tronvillain:
You claim that the author is attempting to sneak the conclusion of the argument into one or more of his premises. You quote premise 2 then comment: Quote:
What about premise 2 presupposes determinism? You have confused this premise with what one gets when one combines this premise with determinism. Next, you say: Quote:
How does premise 1 presuppose determinism? What does it say that entails determinism or is entailed by determinism? It only entails the denial of determinism when it is combined with other premises. Think of it this way. The author is saying that of the 4 premises you must reject at least one of them. He believes this because when they are combined the argument yields determinism and its denial. He thinks that premises 1,2, and 4 are much more plausible than the premise which states determinism. [ June 02, 2002: Message edited by: Taffy Lewis ]</p> |
||
06-02-2002, 03:59 PM | #36 | ||
Regular Member
Join Date: May 2002
Location: North America
Posts: 203
|
bd-from-kg:
You make essentially the same mistake as tronvillain so this post will basically repeat the comments of my last post. You say: Quote:
So the author thinks that one gets a contradictory result when one combines determinism with the other premises. That's what the author means when he says that determinism is self defeating. You almost see the point when you say: Quote:
|
||
06-02-2002, 07:57 PM | #37 | ||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Oct 2000
Location: Alberta, Canada
Posts: 5,658
|
Taffy Lewis:
Quote:
Again, let us look at premise three: Quote:
Now, let us again look at premise two: Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
So, do they mean the same thing by "should"? Apparently not, unless we wish to propose that it is probability one that we will believe only propositions for which we have adequate justification! So, the argument does not follow. END OF STORY. You can make almost any one of the premises false, depending on which ones you start with and what interpretations you are forced to take as a result. [ June 02, 2002: Message edited by: tronvillain ]</p> |
||||||
06-02-2002, 08:07 PM | #38 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Oct 2000
Location: Alberta, Canada
Posts: 5,658
|
|
06-02-2002, 09:57 PM | #39 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Taffy Lewis:
OK, one last time. We have: (P1) Everyone should always refrain from believing falsehoods. (P2) Whatever should be done can be done. (P3) If determinism is true, then whatever can be done, is done. The third is true by definition, so it is a necessary truth. In other words, these premises can be written as follows: (1*) (for all P)((P is false) implies (for all A)(A should disbelieve P)) (2*) (for all X)((X should be done) implies (X can be done)) (3*) (Determinism is true) entails (for all X) ((X can be done) implies (X is done)) Now let’s see what these premises logically entail. First, combining (2*) and (3*) yields: (C1) (Determinism is true) entails (for all X)(X should be done) implies (X is done)) Next, combining (1*) and (C1) yields: (C2) (Determinism is true) entails (for all P)((P is false) implies (for all A)(A disbelieves P)) C2 can be restated in plain English as: “Determinism entails that all beliefs are true”. C2 is rigorously entailed by P1, P2, and P3. But it is plainly false. If a false statement is entailed by a set of premises, one of the premises must be false. Therefore either P1, P2, or P3 is false. If this is still to hard for you, I can only recommend a course in Logic 101. |
06-03-2002, 02:57 AM | #40 | |
Regular Member
Join Date: May 2002
Location: North America
Posts: 203
|
bd-from-kg:
Quote:
|
|
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|