Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
06-27-2003, 10:11 AM | #131 | |||||||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Clutch:
Hate to be a pest, but this subject is pretty close to the heart of the point of this thread, so it seems to me to be worth pursuing. And no one else seems to be doing it. [By the way, to avoid any misunderstanding on the point, I am not supporting theism. The fact that principles for evaluating empirical claims are not themselves empirical claims doesn’t imply anything at all about the existence of God, and it certainly doesn’t support presuppositionalism, which I consider to be out there in la-la land.] Part 1: I might as well go ahead and make what few comments seem appropriate on the last part of your June 24 post. Quote:
Quote:
As if the circularity weren’t bad enough, the “principle” in this case is a value judgment, so it doesn’t make sense to try to “justify” it anyway. Quote:
Part 2: Now on to your June 25 post. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
But I don’t see the relevance of whether some such principles fail strictly “by the lights of other such principles”. If the principles for evaluating empirical claims (taken as a whole) should fail such an empirical test, they fail; the details of how they failed wouldn’t matter. What matters is: what should we conclude from such a failure? Let’s take the Principle of Induction as an example (since it’s simple and basic, and has been analyzed to death). Suppose that it’s possible to show (on some possible world) that the Principle of Induction fails. What follows? I’d say that what would follow is that rational evaluation of empirical claims is impossible in that world. If a world is so chaotic that induction consistently gives results no better than chance, rational creature could not exist there, and if they somehow did, they would be completely helpless. There would be no way for them to learn anything about their world (beyond their current, immediate perceptions) or to function effectively (i.e., to pursue goals, to influence events in ways they consider desirable). The same thing would follow from the failure of any other principle for evaluating empirical claims that might conceivably fail in this way. (Many, like Ockham’s Razor and Sagan’s dictum, are such that it’s logically impossible for them to “fail”.) Thus in saying that these principles are valid, we are not saying that they will “work” in all possible worlds, but that they will work in any possible world which is capable of being understood rationally. And moreover, that they represent the “best strategy” in the absence of any information about the world (which is necessarily the situation we all have to start from). Thus following these principles is the only viable option for a rational being; if they don’t work, no rational strategy will work. But none of this changes the fact that the principles for evaluating empirical claims cannot be empirically validated. They represent (taken as a whole) the rational strategy for understanding the world, and can be justified as logically necessary components of that strategy. That’s not an empirical justification; it’s an a priori justification. Quote:
Please don’t assume that everyone here is as much of a scholar as you. This isn’t a symposium of professional philosophers. The general rule around here is that if you’re going to appeal to authority (which is what you’re doing here) you need to give at least a general outline of the main arguments that the authority used to support the conclusion in question. Otherwise the “Evolution” forum would shut down very quickly after it was pointed out that “virtually everyone” (i.e., virtually all competent biologists) believes in it. Quote:
Quote:
In other words, we can separate the questions: (1) How probable is it that H is true? (2) Shall I act as though H is true? Sometimes you can hedge your bets; you don’t have to act either in a way that will only further your ends if H is true or in another way that will only do so if H is false. But sometimes you are faced with this stark choice, although you may have some room to maneuver: you can postpone the decision for a while until more information comes in. All of these things can be very important to get right. But they all relate to (2), not to (1). Quote:
Quote:
Now you say that we can at least test the dictum for “consistency”. But if it’s not an empirical claim this doesn’t make sense; it simply doesn’t matter what the result is. By way of analogy, suppose that the Supreme Court says, “No one is above the law; we all have to abide by the law”. Someone objects, “But in the final analysis the law is what the Supreme Court has said it is. And the Supreme Court itself doesn’t always abide by what the Supreme Court has said; it sometimes reverses its earlier decisions. So the Supreme Court is violating its own dictum.” The answer to this, of course, is that the statement was not intended to refer to the decisions of the Supreme Court itself. The fact that the Supreme Court doesn’t abide by its own previous decisions may look like an inconsistency at first sight, but it’s not. In fact, if Sagan’s dictum were an empirical claim, theophilus’s objection could be disposed of very quickly: we would simply test it empirically. The only reason the objection is even superficially plausible is that this hasn’t been done. And it hasn’t been done because it can’t be done, because it’s not an empirical claim. Quote:
Quote:
|
|||||||||||||
06-30-2003, 07:57 AM | #132 | |||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Oct 2001
Location: Canada
Posts: 3,751
|
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
"Does the prosecution claim that Smith was at the scene and committed the murder, or that Smith was at the scene or committed the murder?" "Aww, Judge, you're taking this logical structure business way too seriously!" For pete's sake, bd. You introduced a big, complex statement, to use it in a refutation. Whether it's a big, complex "and" statement, or a big, complex "or" statement, is sort of important. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
|
|||||||
07-02-2003, 08:07 AM | #133 | ||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Clutch:
This is a reply to your June 26 post. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
If “testing” a hypothesis meant showing directly that any postulated entities really exist in addition to showing that the predictions it generates are correct, no scientific hypothesis could be tested, because this type of test is impossible in principle. All we can ever do is to compare predictions to actual outcomes. That’s the nature of scientific theories. They typically postulate various entities (the electroweak force, quarks) whose supposed existence is manifested only in various observable phenomena; they are not themselves observable. Such theories (like all scientific theories) are considered to be confirmed when their predictions match observations and disconfirmed when they don’t. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Of course, I suspect that Sagan was really referring to “dragon-in-the-garage”-type untestable claims, which are not associated with any physical theory and are worthless in all respects. The only reason I got into the other kind is to show that your “u,i,u One” example doesn’t refute my argument. It’s a perfectly good, testable hypothesis by any criterion that I know of, and the success of predictions based on it supports it, just as it would any other testable hypothesis. Any hypothesis that helps to produce testable predictions is, by definition, part of (or associated with) a physical theory, and is testable simply by checking the predictions. In short, your argument fails. Your supposed counterexample isn’t a counterexample, and once one understands why it’s not a counterexample it should be clear why there cannot be any counterexamples. |
||||||||
07-02-2003, 08:31 AM | #134 | |||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Clutch:
Rather than replying to your last post point by point, I think it would be best to take your last statement as a springboard for recapping my argument. Quote:
As for (2), the principle involved is extremely simple: it’s the principle of “You can’t find out whether a person is truthful by asking him.” Now of course, in a sense you can sometimes tell whether a person is truthful by asking him – namely if he replies, “No, I’m not.” But if he replies, “Yes, I am” you learn nothing beyond the fact that he doesn’t contradict himself. Now let’s ignore for the moment the possibility that a principle for evaluating empirical claims is self-contradictory, or that given the evidence it “declares itself” to be false, and consider what it would mean to say that it’s confirmed by the evidence. Surely this can only mean that the rules for evaluating empirical evidence, taken as a whole, instruct us to follow such-and-such a procedure, and that the principle is confirmed if the results satisfy a certain description and disconfirmed if they don’t. If we follow this procedure for every principle for evaluating empirical claims, the best possible result is that all of them are strongly confirmed. But what does this mean really? It means that the principles for evaluating empirical claims (taken as a whole) tell us that they’re true. And this “evidence” is just as good as the evidence that a man provides of his truthfulness by assuring us that he’s truthful. Which to say that it’s no good at all. But this means that it’s impossible in principle to verify such principles empirically. Note that we’re not talking here about proving empirically that these principles are valid; nothing can be proved empirically. We’re asking only for evidence sufficient to justify rational belief. The fact that they "declare themselves" to be valid isn’t even close to being sufficient to justify rational belief, any more than that fact that someone assures you that he’s truthful is sufficient in itself to justify rational belief that he is. The only possible conclusion from all of this, it seems to me, is that our confidence in the validity of these principles is not based on empirical evidence. And that means that they are not empirical claims. Now for a couple of side points: (1) It should be clear from the above why the “logical structure of Eval” is irrelevant. What matters is that by definition the principles for evaluating empirical claims yield a procedure for evaluating any given empirical claim. In fact, without a procedure for testing a claim, it cannot be called an empirical claim at all. So if these principles do not yield a procedure for evaluating a claim the only possible conclusions are that the claim is too vague to constitute an empirical claim, or that it simply isn’t, by it’s very nature, an empirical claim. (2) A couple of posts back I presented this argument: Quote:
Your latest post explains what you think is wrong with this argument as follows: Quote:
|
|||
07-02-2003, 10:04 AM | #135 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Oct 2001
Location: Canada
Posts: 3,751
|
bd,
You are right to say that you have simply repeated your arguments. For reasons I've already given, they are not compelling. I've tried several times now to see where they rise above question-begging or simple non-sequitur, but I can't. So I'm afraid I have it to leave it at the explanations I've already given, and allow that the fault may be mine for not finding the cogency you evidently find in your reasoning. |
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|