Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
05-19-2003, 03:20 PM | #11 | |||
Contributor
Join Date: Dec 2002
Location: Alaska!
Posts: 14,058
|
Quote:
I was quoting Friend, except that I substituted the word "objective" where he used "subjective." I agree with you that he probably meant that that if subjective morality were true there wouldn't be any way to tell right from wrong. But that's what he meant (I think). What I meant is that subjective morality doesn't have any problems that objective morality doesn't have. In this particular case I mean that if you can't tell right from wrong using subjective morality, then you can't tell right from wrong using objective morality. Quote:
Suppose I decide that hitting people with baseball bats is moral. Most people would call that subjective morality because it depends on my personal decision. By your definition, it is objective morality because I can be perfectly sure that I decided it was moral. crc |
|||
05-19-2003, 03:37 PM | #12 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Alonzo Fyfe:
I agree with your latest post but have some comments about the terminology that you defined in your earlier one. This terminology is nonstandard and thus likely to lead to confusion (especially since my post used the standard terminology). First, a moral theory is called “objective” if it holds that moral statements (such as “It is right for John to do Y”) have a definite truth value (the same one for everyone) independent of what anyone thinks, believes, or feels. “Objective” and “subjective” are not antonyms in this context. It is quite possible for a moral theory to be neither objective nor subjective, as you pointed out. Your “subjective(1)” is referred to by moral philosophers as “non-cognitive”. In particular, “emotive” theories are classed as one type of noncognitive theory (there are other types), not a variety of subjective moral theory. Your “subjective (3)” is known as “non-realist” in the standard terminology. (Many realist moral theories hold that some states of affairs are “intrinsically preferable” to others, independently of whether anyone does in fact prefer them, or even whether anyone would prefer them under appropriate conditions, such as having sufficient insight or understanding. In these versions of moral realism an act is “right” if it leads to a state of affairs that is intrinsically preferable to the states of affairs produced by all alternatives. Whether this is properly referred to as an intrinsic property of the act or of its consequences is not really important here.) Objective moral theories are often realist, but it is quite possible to hold that moral statements have definite truth values but do not refer to intrinsic properties of the acts in question (or of their consequences). Subjective theories are one type of non-realist theory, but so are noncognitive theories and some objective theories. Your subjective(2) is one type of “subjective” moral theory. More generally, a subjective theory interprets moral statements as statements about the feelings or attitudes (or some other mental disposition) of some person or group of persons (not necessarily that of the speaker) toward the act in question. Your moral theory is objective but non-realist. (By the way, I’m a noncognitivist, but not of the “emotivist” variety.) Finally, Friend’s question "Do you believe moral values are objective?" seems to be asking whether (we believe) there is such a thing as “intrinsic goodness”. We agree that there is no such thing - in fact, that all versions of moral realism are false. |
05-19-2003, 08:55 PM | #13 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Sep 2001
Location: Sri Dunka ....
Donut: Cruller w/Jimmies
Posts: 2,710
|
Re: Morality and supreme law
Quote:
Can an objective moral system be "good?" "Moral? " How so? |
|
05-20-2003, 04:53 AM | #14 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: 920B Milo Circle
Lafayette, CO
Posts: 3,515
|
Quote:
Outside of a philosophy department, I almost never encounter distinctions such as "cognitivism/non-cognitivism" and "realism/anti-realism". There are only two terms in use; "objective" and "subjective". "Objective" includes the scientific sense of objectivity, cognitivism, and realism. "Subjective" incorporates non-cognitivism, psychological subjectivity, and anti-realism. Friend's original question illustrates this, where he uses 'objective' in the realist sense, rather than the scientific sense. Using philosophy-department language in a non-philosophy-department setting is little different from using a foreign language. It does not prevent confusion, it helps feed confusion. However, even within a philosophy department, the distinction is not clear. David Brink's definition of moral realism, for example, would count all objective theories as realist. His criteria are: (1) There are moral facts or truths, and (2) These facts or truths are independent of our evidence for them. In a footnote, Brink pretty much uses the terms 'realism' and 'cognitivism' interchangeably -- though he counts a type of cognitive theory (Mackie's error theory) as anti-realist. There are important ambiguities in this distinction -- such as with the phrase 'independent of our evidence for them'. Does this mean 'independent of our psychological states'? If it does then, by definition, all psychological theories are anti-realist by definition. Yet, this is too restrictive. Does he really want to say that realism about beliefs and desires is impossible by definition? Yet, the instant that we allow for the possibility of realism with respect to desires, then desire-dependent value immediately becomes a realist theory. Geoffrey Sayer-McCord offers a different definition of realism. (1) The claims in question, when literally construed, are literally true or false. (2) Some are literally true. Combine this with the view that value-claims, when literally construed, include a claim of intrinsic prescriptivity, and you can get a view that allows one to be a realist about desires, but an anti-realist about values. But one runs into problems in a number of scientific areas. For example, the word 'atom' originally meant 'indivisible particle'. Literally construed, we would have to say that those who first thought that atoms had parts were anti-realists about atoms. Similarly, the word 'malaria' originally meant 'bad air'. It was built into the very definition of the term that this disease was caused by bad air. Those who theorized that 'malaria' was caused by bacteria had to be classified as anti-realists about malaria. These results seem odd at best. Realism should allow one to be an anti-realist about unsplittable atoms and bad-air malaria, without being anti-realists about atoms and malaria. Yet, this implies that realism should allow one to be an anti-realist about intrinsic-prescriptivity moral values without being an anti-realist about moral values. The point being even within the philosophy department, the distinction between realism and objectivism is confusing. I do not think that the confusion is restricted entirely to my particular use of these terms. |
|
05-20-2003, 11:18 AM | #15 | ||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Alonzo Fyfe:
Quote:
If you’re going to make careful distinctions, the “target audience” is going to consist of those who are seriously interested in such things, and these are just the people who have either read some works on moral philosophy or are probably going to. The former don’t need your lecture; all they’ll get out of it is that you use nonstandard terminology and that if they want to understand you they had better memorize your nonstandard usage even though it will be useless baggage elsewhere. The latter will (at best) learn your usage and then have to unlearn it later when they start reading moral philosophy. Who benefits? Quote:
With regard to the terms “objective” and “subjective” in moral philosophy, these usages are really quite standard. As for your other comments, they appear to be, in effect, complaints about the fact that some terms (including “objective”, “subjective”, and “realist”) are not used in moral philosophy with exactly the same meaning as elsewhere (including other areas of philosophy). This is just a fact; it is rooted both in the history of moral philosophy and in practical considerations. There’s no point in complaining about it. |
||
05-20-2003, 02:49 PM | #16 | |||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: 920B Milo Circle
Lafayette, CO
Posts: 3,515
|
Quote:
Quote:
It seems to me that, while the academic philosopher does good work, their findings are not getting communicated to the public. An academic philosopher will dismiss divine-command theories of ethics with a single word, "Euthyphro". For nearly three centuries they have been dismissing "most vulgar systems of morality" by a simple reference to "the is/ought distinction." Yet, these findings tend not to make it far outside the philosophy department. That problem . . . interests me. Quote:
So, I do not get the sense that even moral philosophers are in as much universal agreement on their use of terms as you seem to think. But, I do not think that such an issue is worth huge quantities of debate. It is worth while to come up with a less confusing terminology. This is simply my most recent experiment. After looking at the results, I may (probably will) try something else later. |
|||
05-20-2003, 08:09 PM | #17 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Nov 2001
Location: Denver
Posts: 1,774
|
A problem? You guys are on cloud nine. Whatever morality is, or whatever you guys pretend to be talking about, if it can’t be communicated then it might as well be Greek. You’re living in a tower of babble, and bd-from-kg that’s a shame because you’re a very talented writer.
|
05-23-2003, 12:29 PM | #18 | |||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
wiploc:
Quote:
intractable. One has to determine what the total effects of an action will be into the indefinite future and evaluate somehow which set of total effects is “best”. Or one has to determine the intentions of a mysterious, invisible being who has left (at best) only the most sketchy, confusing guidelines on the subject. (By contrast, His instructions on the proper way to conduct sacrifices are very clear, detailed, and extensive. Kinda makes you wonder.) Quote:
Quote:
Just the same, the requirement that moral statements must have a truth value which is “observer-independent” (which is part of what it means for a moral theory to be “objective”) is the same as what is normally meant by saying that a statement is “objectively true or false”. And this part of the meaning, taken by itself, is enough to show that (in an objective moral system) there must be some procedure which in principle can be carried out for determining the truth of moral statements. |
|||
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|