Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
11-08-2002, 05:52 PM | #11 | ||
Regular Member
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: USA
Posts: 274
|
Quote:
Quote:
Jeffery Jay Lowder |
||
11-08-2002, 05:57 PM | #12 | |
Regular Member
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: USA
Posts: 274
|
Quote:
Jeffery Jay Lowder |
|
11-09-2002, 07:41 AM | #13 | ||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Oct 2001
Location: Canada
Posts: 3,751
|
Quote:
I thought that was your point. Again, it does not seem to impinge on bd's point, which is charitably understood to be that mere semantic ascent does not make a moral principle itself truth-apt. The truth-claim itself is may or may not be considered truth-apt, depending upon whether "is true" is used as a sentential or a propositional operator. So: 1) Boogala boogala! [meaningless] 2) It is objectively true that boogala boogala. [meaningless] 3) "Boogala boogala" is objectively true. [false] When he wrote, Quote:
I took bd's point to be that (2) is no better than (1) with respect to being meaningful. And that seems correct. |
||
11-09-2002, 08:08 AM | #14 | |
Regular Member
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: USA
Posts: 274
|
Quote:
Jeffery Jay Lowder |
|
11-09-2002, 10:01 AM | #15 | |||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
jlowder:
This is a fuller reply to your long post of Nov. 8. Quote:
In your latest post you say that if S does not express a proposition it is not meaningless but false to say that S is objectively true. This is just a linguistic quibble, but I don’t agree with this usage. “S”, “S is true” and “It is objectively true that S” are generally taken to be logically equivalent, so if one of them is meaningless, all of them are. Thus I would say that if “Stealing is wrong” is meaningless, “It is objectively true that stealing is wrong" is also meaningless. But if you prefer to say that if “Stealing is wrong” is meaningless, “It is objectively true that stealing is wrong” is false, so be it, as long as we understand one another. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
But if saying that the moral property of “rightness” supervenes on the natural property of “healthiness” is not just a fancy way of defining “rightness” to mean “healthiness”, we are left with the problem of what kind of property “rightness” is. If it were a natural property, why talk about moral properties “supervening” on natural properties at all? Why not just say what natural property “rightness” is? Why not just say, “To say that an act is ‘right’ means that it has the natural property Q”, rather than saying “The moral property of ‘rightness’ supervenes on the natural property Q”? Thus it only makes sense to speak of moral properties “supervening” on natural properties if moral properties are not themselves natural properties. And this leaves us with the vexing question of what kind of properties moral properties are. This is the problem that G.E. Moore saw quite clearly, and why he took the position that “goodness” is not a natural property at all, but a simple, unanalyzable, non-natural property. Quote:
When different moral objectivists disagree about such questions; when they give completely different accounts of what kind of property “rightness” is, or what kind of property a criterion of rightness would have to be, or how to distinguish the “true” criterion of rightness from the many imposters, it is fair to say that they disagree profoundly about what it means to say that a moral principle is objectively true. It seems odd, to put it mildly, to argue that moral statements are objectively true without being able to give even a rudimentary account of what it is that they assert. The noncognitivist argument is that no such account, or no remotely plausible one anyway, is possible. To answer this argument the objectivist needs to show that there is at least one plausible account of what such statements mean. Quote:
One last point. In your nest-to-last last post you said: Quote:
Clutch: Thanks for the clarifications. Your explanations seem to be much more concise than mine. In fact, if I hadn’t had further points to make, I’d have been content to just say “what he said”. |
|||||||
11-09-2002, 10:34 AM | #16 | |||||||||||
Regular Member
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: USA
Posts: 274
|
I'm going to respond to one portion of bd-from-kg's post now, and save the rest for later.
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Returning to the subject of Post and his book, I know that Post is well-respected by other philosophers. (<a href="http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/quentin_smith/" target="_blank">Quentin Smith</a> is one of the Internet Infidels Supporters and a very highly regarded atheist philosopher who also just happens to highly endorse Post's book. I think that should give anyone pause who thinks Post's book is "garbage.") Since moral philosophy is a branch of philosophy in general, I value the opinions of other professional philosophers, especially morally philosophers, regarding the quality of philosophy books (including Post's book) much more than I value the opinions of non-philosophers. (By analogy, if a non-mathematician were to declare that Einstein's mathematical theories were "garbage," who cares what the non-mathematician thinks? Why should we even regard the non-mathematician as competent on the subject?) The fact that you would dismiss a book you have never read as "garbage" sounds like the sort of comment a non-philosopher would make, a comment I do not place much value in. (Are you a philosopher? Have you at least taken any college-level courses in moral philosophy? And just to pre-empt a possible reply: No, I am not a philosopher but I have a taken a college-level course in moral philosophy. Moreover, I am not calling books by professional philosophers "garbage.") Moreover, although appealing to Post as an authority in an attempt to settle a debate on this board would be fallacious, Post nevertheless is an authority who defends moral realism, and critics of moral realism should at least be familiar with his arguments. Anyone who wants to reject moral realism (or, more broadly, moral cognitivism) should at least be familiar with Post's arguments, just as any creationist who wants to reject evolution should at least be familiar with authorities on evolutionary biology (e.g., Richard Dawkins), just as any moral realist who wants to reject moral subjectivism should at least be familiar with authorities on subjectivism (e.g., J.L. Mackie). Indeed, one could just as easily reply, "Until you convince me that you are actually familiar with the arguments of the leading moral realists, I’m going to assume that your arguments against moral realism are garbage." Quote:
Again, I have already summarized his argument on this board. For convenience, I will summarize it again. John Post describes his argument as follows: Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
So that's Post's thesis. What is Post's argument for his thesis? The first premise of the argument appeals to the "weak supervenience" of the moral on the natural: Quote:
Quote:
The determinacy of valuation follows from the conjunction of EP and MEA. And if Post's thesis about the determinacy of valuation is correct, then it follows that moral realism is true. As a syllogism, Post's argument looks like this: (1) EP (2) MEA (3) If EP and MEA, then the determinacy of valuation is true. (4) Therefore, the determinacy of valuation is true. (from 1, 2, and 3) (5) If the determinacy of valuation is true, moral realism is true. (6) Therefore, moral realism is true. (from 4 and 5) You may disagree with this argument. Hell, you may think it is the worst argument you have ever seen. But don't ever tell me I am hiding behind some authority, whose arguments I am unwilling to summarize, since I clearly have summarized the relevant arguments. Quote:
Jeffery Jay Lowder [ November 09, 2002: Message edited by: jlowder ] [ November 09, 2002: Message edited by: jlowder ] (edited a third time to discuss the relationship between propositions and truth values) [ November 10, 2002: Message edited by: jlowder ]</p> |
|||||||||||
11-09-2002, 12:02 PM | #17 | ||||||||||||||
Regular Member
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: USA
Posts: 274
|
Here is my reply to another portion of bd-from-kg's post, a portion which dealt with the concepts of supervenience and meta-ethics in general:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Moreover, notice that when they do provide such an account, they have stepped out of the domain of meta-ethics and into the domain of normative ethics. From the perspective of meta-ethics, why can't the moral objectivists simply say that moral propositions are true just in case they correspond to the facts. If one then asks, "Yes, but which facts?", the moral objectivist could then respond, "That depends upon which normative ethical theory is correct; normative ethical theories specify the exact identity of moral properties. According to my normative ethical theory, the criterion of rightness is X," where X is determined by the normative ethical theory of the speaker. Quote:
Quote:
Jeffery Jay Lowder (edited by adding the discussion of what a meta-ethical theory should be able to provide) [ November 09, 2002: Message edited by: jlowder ]</p> |
||||||||||||||
11-10-2002, 05:32 AM | #18 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Oct 2001
Location: Canada
Posts: 3,751
|
JJL,
I think you are making a use-mention error. (2) is indeed meaningless. It uses the string 'boogala boogala'. Since that phrase is meaningless, there is no compositional interpretation of the sentence that returns a complete proposition, hence no truth-apt interpretation of it. (3), by contrast, places that string in quotation marks, creating a name for it. So (3) mentions the string 'boogala boogala'. It says of a named item that it is true. Since that item is not meaningful, and thus not true, the sentence is false. |
11-10-2002, 03:52 PM | #19 | |||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
jlowder:
Quote:
Quote:
Note: Once again I was being sloppy in describing the issue as being whether value judgments are determined by physical facts. In the first place, it may well be that value judgments are physical facts. The real issue is whether the correctness of value judgments is determined by natural facts. But even this could be misinterpreted. Actually almost everyone agrees that if there are moral facts they do supervene on natural facts. As someone put it, once we have the natural facts, the moral facts come for free. The difference between naturalistic and non-naturalistic moral objectivists is not about whether moral facts are determined by physical facts, but about the nature of moral facts. For example, some philosophers have claimed that moral properties such as “goodness” and “rightness” are non-natural properties which have the peculiar feature that whether an act or state of affairs has such a property follows from its natural properties, but cannot be identified with any combination of or relationship between them. Although such theories entail that moral facts are determined by physical facts, they are not naturalistic theories. On the other hand, the position that “goodness” and “rightness” not only supervene on natural properties, but are themselves natural properties, defines moral naturalism. Now as to my “garbage” comment, it should have been obvious that I am not familiar with Post’s work since the whole point was why I did not intend to become familiar with his work unless you convinced me that it would be worth my time. So this could not have been meant as an evaluation of his work. As to whether you’d call the work of this or that philosopher “garbage”, this is beside the point; we don’t all use language the same way. What I mean by “garbage” in this context is that it’s not worth my time, and therefore is worthless to me. All that I meant was that I would assume that it would not be worth my time to read his book (because as far as I know it has nothing interesting and original to say) unless you could show me something that would convince me otherwise. Quote:
Anyway, from what I’ve seen so far it appears that I am familiar with his arguments; I’m just not familiar with his particular exposition of them. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Now perhaps we are ready to actually talk about moral philosophy. As to the part of Post’s argument that you do quote, it shows only that if there are objective moral facts, they supervene on natural facts, which as I pointed out earlier is hardly controversial. For example, here’s G.E. Moore: Quote:
Note: Post actually says “... for a moral rule to be true (or correct or to be followed”. I’m not sure what he means by saying that a moral rule is “to be followed” as opposed to being “true”, but this sounds strikingly like the sort of thing that I might say about a moral principle. To say that the rule “Do not break promises” is a rule to be followed is not to say that it is “true”, or even that it expresses a proposition. In fact, it’s not at all clear that “Moral rule R is to be followed” expresses a proposition; it seems to me to be a prescription, closer in meaning to “Follow rule R” than to “R has such-and-such a property”. At any rate, if Post intends “to be followed” to have a meaning such that “Moral rule R is to be followed” expresses a proposition, I’d like to know what it is, and what proposition he intends this statement to express. It certainly is not intended to express the proposition that moral rule R is true, or he wouldn’t have bothered to make this distinction. Also, what does he mean by distinguishing between a moral rule’s being “true” and “correct”? As for MEA, I have no idea why Post says “If we pretend our moral judgments are true or false...” as opposed to “if our moral judgments are true or false...”. Why should anything of interest follow from our pretending that moral statements are true or false? But in any case, it is transparent that MEA also assumes moral objectivity; after all, it says that of various differing moral judgments, one is “correct”. But again, this is gibberish unless it makes sense to speak of a moral judgment as being “correct”. Now as for the final argument, it seems to be valid and may be sound, but it is utterly unpersuasive because the conclusion is contained so transparently in the premises. To illustrate the problem, consider these two arguments: P1: “God exists” is true, “God is omnipotent” is true. P2: “God exists” is true. C: “God is omnipotent” is true. P1: If “God exists” is not true, “God is omnipotent” is not true. P2: “God exists” is not true. C: “God is omnipotent” is not true. Now both of these arguments are perfectly valid, and one of them is sound. But neither of them is at all persuasive, because anyone who does not already accept the conclusion of one of them is certainly not going to accept the premises either. So it is with Post’s argument (or rather the argument that you offer on his behalf). Why would anyone who is not already a moral realist accept EP or MEA? It’s hardly surprising that one can “prove” that moral realism is true from premises that presume the truth of moral realism. The real question is what arguments Post has for EP and MEA. I imagine that he must have some, but so far you have failed to present them. |
|||||||
11-10-2002, 03:58 PM | #20 | |||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
jlowder:
1. Supervenience and its relationship to naturalistic ethics Quote:
Talking about moral properties “supervening” on natural properties appears to me to be an attempt to get around the problem by saying that “rightness” is not identical to the natural property in question, but only “supervenes” on it. But this only helps if “rightness” is not itself a natural property; otherwise the same argument applies to the property of “rightness” itself. And if it is not a natural property, we’re back to the problem of what kind of property it is. Again, an illustration might be helpful here. According to classical utilitarianism, an act is “right” is and only if it produces more happiness than any of the available alternatives. (This is an oversimplification, but it will do for the purpose.) Now as G.E. Moore pointed out, this can be interpreted in two different ways: (i) saying that an act is “right” means that it conduces to the greatest happiness, or (ii) acts that are “right” always in fact have the property that they conduce to the greatest happiness, and no other acts have this property. In the second case we could say that “rightness” supervenes on the property of “conducing to the greatest happiness”, while in the first we would say that “rightness” is this property. But the first interpretation is open to the objection above: it seems clear that it makes sense to agree that an act conduces to the greatest happiness yet question whether it is right. (In fact a great many moral philosophers have questioned this, to put it mildly.) Contrast this with agreeing that a polygon has three sides, yet questioning whether it is really a triangle. This strikes us as ludicrous, precisely because saying that something is a triangle means that it is a polygon with three sides. The second interpretation is open to the very same objection if “rightness” is just another natural property that supervenes on “conducing to the greatest happiness” in the same way that entropy supervenes on other natural properties. If it is a natural property, it can be defined in purely descriptive, naturalistic terms that do not involve any moral or evaluative terminology; call this description D. But no matter what this description looks like, it is clearly sensible to agree that an act satisfies this description, yet question whether it is right. It might be true as a matter of fact that all right actions (and no wrong ones) satisfy this description – i.e., satisfying D may be an infallible indicator that an act is right - but “X satisfies D” cannot be a correct definition of what it means for an act to be morally right. But if “rightness” is not a natural property, but merely supervenes on a natural property, then we are not talking about a naturalistic moral theory, and we have to give some plausible, logically coherent account of what kind of property it is. 2. The role of metaethics Since you questioned all of my statements about what a metaethical theory should be able to do, it will probably be more helpful to explain my conception of the role of metaethics. Metaethical questions are hardly the first kinds of questions that occur to us when we start to think seriously about ethics. The kinds of questions that we start with are typically ones of “practical ethics”, such as whether capital punishment is right or wrong, or whether abortion should be legal. But in discussing such questions we find that not only do people disagree about such questions, but they offer entirely different kinds of justifications for their positions. Some might argue, for example, that capital punishment is right because it has desirable consequences; others that it is right because justice demands it regardless of consequences; others that it is wrong because it violates the sanctity of life or because it is forbidden by God’s commandments. This leads one naturally to consider the questions of normative ethics: What moral principles are valid? Or ultimately, what is the criterion of “rightness”; what quality or property of an act determines whether it is right or wrong? But here once again we encounter profound disagreements; some say that some moral principles are valid while others deny that they are and offer entirely different moral principles in their stead. Worse yet, they disagree about what makes a moral principle valid. This leads us to the fundamental question of metaethics: what does it mean to say that a moral principle is valid? When we reflect on how we got to this point, we recall that the original purpose was to work out answers to questions such as whether capital punishment is wrong, and that this led us to ask how we can distinguish valid moral principles from invalid ones, and that this led us in turn to ask what it means to say that a moral principle is valid. So in answering the latter question we must keep in mind that the point of asking is was to help us to distinguish between valid moral principles and invalid ones, and ultimately to distinguish between right acts and wrong ones. Thus we have not done what we set out to do until we have found an answer to the question of what it means to say that a moral principle is valid that is clear and concrete enough to at least offer some meaningful guidance in answering the question of what moral principles are valid. An answer to the former question that fails to provide any such guidance is at best radically incomplete. Thus the various “levels” of moral philosophy: practical ethics, normative ethics, and metaethics, are not independent enterprises, but are closely interconnected. The purpose of each of the “higher” levels is to help us to answer questions at the “lower” levels. A normative theory should help us answer the questions of practical ethics; a theory that offers little or no such guidance is at best radically incomplete. In the same way, a metaethical theory that offers little or no guidance in helping to distinguish between true and false (or as I would say, valid and invalid) moral principles is unsatisfactory because it fails to fulfill the function or purpose of a metaethical theory. Quote:
3. Objectivism and noncognitivism Quote:
Quote:
Now certainly there are many aspects of the logic of moral discourse that seem to imply that moral statements are intended to express propositions – i.e., to say that certain things are “objectively true”. But there are other aspects of moral discourse that seem to imply otherwise. It seems clear to me that there is no logically coherent interpretation of ordinary moral discourse that fully captures or corresponds to what most people who use it seem to intend, or in other words that there is no plausible account of what such statements mean to those who use them. (This is, after all, the real question. Anyone can invent a new meaning for moral statements. I can say that “Doing X is right” means that X is the first thing that the agent does after the sun rises, or that it involves turning to the right. But a personal, private interpretation that ignores actual usage is of no interest to anyone but its inventor.) Quote:
As for the various theories you mention, I certainly don’t intend to try here and now to refute every such attempt. Suffice it to say that I don’t think that any of these attempts are successful. Moreover, I don’t think that any such attempt can be successful, for the reasons already given and for others that I haven’t mentioned yet. [ November 11, 2002: Message edited by: bd-from-kg ]</p> |
|||||
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|