Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
07-13-2002, 08:52 AM | #211 | ||||||||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
John Page:
Quote:
Quote:
Also, almost all moral philosophers agree that this is a necessary condition for a moral theory to be “objective”. Some even seem to imply that it is a sufficient condition. In any case, it’s pretty important. Theories that satisfy this criterion are fundamentally different from ones that do not. Quote:
Quote:
Obviously my theory relates the “rightness” of an act to some possible desires. So does classic utilitarianism. (In fact, John Stuart Mill made this connection explicitly in arguing for the theory.) But the latter is almost universally regarded by moral philosophers as a objective moral theory. Thus, in the context of moral philosophy, the terms “objective” and “subjective” are not used in such a way that theories that relate “rightness” to subjective desires are considered subjective on that account. If you want to use it that way, feel free. But I find that it facilitates communication to use terms in a standard way unless there is a compelling reason not to. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
However, the logic of moral discourse dictates that, if moral statements are expressing propositions, they must be propositions whose truth is independent of who expresses them. Thus, if Smith says “X should do Y and Jones says “X should not do Y”, it just doesn’t make sense to say that both are correct. The logic of moral discourse requires that Smith and Jones are disagreeing. Thus if Smith’s statement expresses a proposition, Jones’s statement expresses the negation of this same proposition. To say, for example, that Smith is merely saying that he has a certain feeling towards X’s doing Y while Jones is merely saying that he does not have this feeling, is incompatible with the way such language is used. It is reasonable to say that neither statement expresses a proposition at all, or it is reasonable to say that the statements express propositions that contradict one another. But it is not reasonable to say that they express propositions that do not contradict one another. In other words, some “noncognitivist” theories appear to be tenable, but most commonly held “subjective” theories of ethics are out of court. Thus I reject most “subjectivist” theories on logical grounds. Quote:
[ July 13, 2002: Message edited by: bd-from-kg ]</p> |
||||||||||||||
07-13-2002, 01:48 PM | #212 | ||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
The AntiChris:
Quote:
Quote:
This kind of problem is inherent in talking about justifying almost any kind of action, in any sense. For example, one might say that the evidence that the planet Neptune exists is compelling, but what does this mean exactly? Any attempt to define it seems to lead to something like this: if a sufficiently rational person were familiar with enough of the relevant evidence, he would be convinced that predictions based on the existence of Neptune can be relied on with a high degree of confidence. Obviously, in the real world no one can be familiar with anything remotely approaching all of the relevant evidence. (And by the way – take note, Alonzo – even if one could there is nothing in the evidence that logically entails that one “should,” [in any sense of “should”] believe that Neptune exists.) And, of course, it is impossible to be sure that there is no evidence that you don’t know of that would indicate that Neptune doesn’t exist after all. Does this difficulty mean that the statement that the evidence for the existence of Neptune is compelling is meaningless? Similarly, one might tell someone that it’s in his best interests to go to college. But what does this mean exactly? Again, any attempt to explain the meaning seems to lead to something like this: if he were sufficiently rational and understood sufficiently well the consequences of going to college and not going, and considered only his own interests, he would choose to go to college. Besides the fact that it may or may not be true in a given case, this has the same problems as the statement about Neptune. It seems that almost any statement to the effect that one “should” do something, if analyzed carefully, turns out to mean something of this sort. So the fact that my analysis of “moral-should” yields something of the same kind should hardly come as a surprise. Unless one is prepared to declare that all such statements are meaningless, this is not a valid criticism of my interpretation. Quote:
Maybe some subjectivists should rethink the way they use the terms “objective” and “subjective” with reference to morality. It’s really rather tiresome to see people making the same old boring point about desires being subjective, etc. We all knew that going in. Anyway, the main point of my theory is that there are objectively valid reasons for acting in certain ways rather than others, which any sufficiently rational person will find compelling. It seems to me that this is significant. Whether one wants to call the theory “objective” or not is of little consequence. What matters is whether it’s true. Quote:
|
||||
07-13-2002, 04:06 PM | #213 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: May 2001
Location: US
Posts: 5,495
|
Quote:
|
|
07-13-2002, 04:26 PM | #214 | ||
Veteran Member
Join Date: May 2001
Location: US
Posts: 5,495
|
Quote:
Quote:
Let's say you live next to a homicidal manic that you know rejects all advances of help by murdering those who try to help. An extreme example I know but my point is: 1. A "rational" person would probably move neighborhoods as soon as possible, immediately if they have kids. 2. A "moral" person sadly enacts your objective moral truth, never to be heard of again. Logic and moral behavior can also be seen at odds in this link to <a href="http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/prisoner-dilemma/" target="_blank">The Prisoners Dilemma</a>, where seemingly logical actions taken to achieve a defined objective result in sub-optimal outcomes. Maybe "logic" isn't as logical as one might think. Thus, your example doesn;t even pass criteria #1. I don't think moral behavior can be treated any differently than any other aspect of reality, one can optimise moral behavior given known circumstances and objectives but stray outside those bounds and you're back in subjectiveland. I'll make a separate post for other parts of your response. Cheers, John [ July 13, 2002: Message edited by: John Page ]</p> |
||
07-13-2002, 06:20 PM | #215 | |||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: May 2001
Location: US
Posts: 5,495
|
Quote:
P.S. You can make about your own interpretation of moral language is being true, but only in the context of your interpretation. Its "objectivity" is thence limited to your interpretation, which itself is subjective. Quote:
I think you human moral behavior can be objectively studied. I think moral behavior can be evaluated in the context of goals or objectives. Objective morality, however, IMO is an oxymoron. Why? Because the behavior itself comes from within the subject. Futhermore, I don't care whether its theistic, non-theistic, humanist or badgers, moral behavior is to do with self-interest. You can include altruism but that amounts to the same thing through vested interest. BTW, I'm still assuming we're using AntiChris's "A common definition of objective is "Existing indepently of the human mind." Quote:
Quote:
Note: Your use of the words "sufficiently rational" in the above is redundant - human behavior is human behavior, period. Is sexism rational? Is racism rational? I could put forward damn good arguments why these biases have become so ingrained in the human psyche but it doesn't make them "right". IMO these are prime examples of why conventional feelgood humanism is a crock, if you start with the premise that humans are intrinsically "good" and can do the "right" thing then you're sunk. Quote:
Consider the evidence, where can I see, feel, hear or touch a "truth"? To rest the case for the existence of an objective morality upon the existence of a objective logical truth (i.e. outside the human mind) doesn't hold water. Cheers, John |
|||||
07-14-2002, 01:30 AM | #216 | ||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
|
bd-from-kg
Quote:
Quote:
Chris |
||
07-14-2002, 02:26 AM | #217 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
|
Quote:
Surely the point is that proponents of objective morality based on intrinsic value clearly would not accept this analogy (how could they in the absence of universal moral consensus?). I'm guessing, but I suspect they'd say that although we're all aware of intrinsic moral value, we often allow self-interest to take precedence. Chris |
|
07-14-2002, 04:01 AM | #218 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
|
bd-from-kg
Quote:
Chris |
|
07-14-2002, 04:10 AM | #219 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: 920B Milo Circle
Lafayette, CO
Posts: 3,515
|
Quote:
Certainly, an increase in knowledge may involve learning that we desire something. But this is not a case of desire derived from knowledge, any more than learning that my brother's care is green means that the greenness of my brother's car is derived from the fact that I looked at the picture. The two following mental states are distinct. A desires that P. A knows that A desires that P. The second state is not considered relevant in explaining action. For example, say I want (desire) some ice-cream, and I believe that there is ice cream in the freezer. This is sufficient (in the absence of counter-weighing desires and physical barriers) for me to go to the freezer and get some ice cream. We do not need to add yet a third mental state, "I believe that I desire some ice cream" in order to cause an action. It may be (and probably is) the case that I believe that I desire some ice cream -- but this is still an extra mental state not needed to explain the action. Psychological literature is fulled with discussions of people who act on desires they do not know they have, and in many cases even deny having. Also, your example of 'carnal knowledcge' is particularly relevant -- animals, for example, desire sex without (we may assume) having any sort of belief at all that they desire sex. But, ultimately, the point of my original statement is that you can not pile any stack of beliefs together, no matter how long, and yield or even weakly infer a desire as a conclusion. If you think it can be done, them simply show me an example. It would take the form: X believes that B(1) X believes that B(2) ... X believes that B(n) ----- Therefore, X desires that D Now, I am not limiting this to strict deductive argument. Any form of induction or abduction is just fine. My point is that the conclusion is a different type of thing and is logically independent of any of the premises. And the thesis that any change in knowledge and belief suggests even in the weakest sense a change in desire is false. [ July 14, 2002: Message edited by: Alonzo Fyfe ]</p> |
|
07-14-2002, 04:39 AM | #220 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: 920B Milo Circle
Lafayette, CO
Posts: 3,515
|
Quote:
Let us assume that you were looking for a fifth physical force in nature -- an extremely weak force, so that its effects are often masked by the four known forces. You would do so by looking for signs of motion that are not fully accounted for by the four existing forces already known to exist. However, if everything you look at can be fully accounted for using the four known forces, then you have no reason to postulate that the fifth force exists. The argument against intrinsic values says that desire is sufficient to explain all intentional action. Nobody can name even the weakest instance of some other force influencing intentional action other than desire. And since desire is a mental state all value is mind-dependent (or subjective, in one relevant sense of the word). I will accept that the ''different cultures disagree' is not the clearest way to present the argument. I think it is better just to cut to the quick and say that in no intentional human action is there even the slightest evidence of an intrinsic value. Because intrinsic value has no explanatory or predictive role to play, it does not exist -- or, more precisely, we have no reason to believe in its existence. Like God, angels, bigfoot, Pegasus, and ghosts, intrinsic values are not relevant to real-world decisions. |
|
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|