Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
09-25-2002, 09:51 AM | #291 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Feb 2001
Location: ""
Posts: 3,863
|
bd-from-kg
moral statements are not propositions Moral statements are declarations that express moral ideas. A proposition, by definition is that which is expressed by a statement. A moral statement makes a moral proposition. Is it therefore correct to state that moral statements are not propositions but are statements that make moral propositions? longbow: I don't understand how you can say that moral statements aren't true or false but then turn around and say that they are a part of reality. Any statement is part of reality. That does not entail that they are true. bd-from-kg If by “a priori proposition” you mean a proposition that can be known to be true independently of any evidence, then yes, all such propositions are analytic. I don't agree with this. How can a proposition be arrived at without consideration of facts and then the same proposition be analytic? First you will have to provide an example of an "a priori proposition" then: (1) demonstrate that whatever ideas it expresses were gained independently of experience (ie through innate ideas or mental faculties) (2) That it is analytic (ie based on Reasoning or acting from a perception of the parts and interrelations of a subject) From the above, it should be clear that a priori propositions can not be analytic. Because there are no moral propositions. Yes there are dear bd, and here is one: "Rape is bad." The following is a moral statement that makes the above moral proposition. "Mike don't rape your girlfriend because rape is bad." Note that the existence of moral propositions does not preclude the existence of moral principles. |
09-25-2002, 11:12 AM | #292 | ||||||||||
Junior Member
Join Date: Sep 2002
Location: Milwaukee
Posts: 99
|
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
I would agree that what "2+3=5" really says is not a statement about the physical world. But, I think the same is true about moral statements even if the statements often include aspects of the physical world. In other words, the reference to the physical world is accidental to moral statements, not essential. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
You cannot possibly be saying that not applying Ockham's Razor could be rational. Would you say that we can define "rational" any way we want to? That would equivocate in practice. I would say "You're not being rational!" And, they would reply with "I AM being rational (according to MY definition)." This would be basically equivalent to the point of contention being "true for them but false for me". Surely there is a common definition of "rational" that we all must be referring to when we use the term and it either includes Ockhams Razor or it doesn't. But, if that is the case, then the statement you are making above is an assertion. And if this is the model for morality, then moral statements are assertions as well. Quote:
|
||||||||||
09-25-2002, 12:37 PM | #293 | |||||||||||||||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Agnos1:
Sorry for the long delay. A don’t have the time I had earlier for this stuff. First, let’s get a couple of side issues out of the way. 1. The nature of consciousness Quote:
2. “Hardwired” behavior Quote:
Quote:
Second, your comments about not trusting authority is rather ironic here. The reason that you find the claim that such behaviors are more or less hard-wired is that you have heard the contrary from people (such as professors) who have presented themselves as authorities on such matters. In reality I think that you’d have a hard time finding serious scientific research purporting to show that such behavior is not “hard-wired” in the sense that humans (or in the first case men) have a genetic predisposition to behave in these ways. Actually it doesn’t take a lot of scientific research to verify that these are innate predispositions. One needs only to look at the behavior of actual human beings. These tendencies are so strong in every society that it requires a willful blindness to fail to recognize them. In what civilization have men not kept women in an inferior status? Where has it not been the nearly universal practice to give preference to members of one’s own race? In fact, the only society that has ever even regarded these things as undesirable and taken some steps to combat them is modern western society. If you say that these behaviors have everywhere been the result of social conditioning, then how did it come to happen that every society has conditioned its members in the same way? History is replete with examples of societies that have differed radically in their organization and prevailing attitudes. It seems inconceivable that they would all have been alike in some important respect by sheer chance. Nor is it reasonable to suppose that some primordial “proto-civilization” was able to influence all of the civilizations that came after it to retain customs and attitudes that do not reflect deep, innate human propensities. Again, when we look at the variety among historical civilizations in so many respects, we are compelled to conclude that any such proto-civilization had very little ability to influence future ones beyond a millennium or two at most. And of course we have the experience of our own civilization, where the cultural elite has been battling both of these tendencies determinedly for some time. But although their more egregious manifestations have been eliminated in some cases, the attitudes themselves have stubbornly resisted these efforts. But before leaving this subject, I want to emphasize two things: A) The fact that a predisposition is “hard-wired” in this sense does not mean that we are all doomed to act accordingly. Upbringing and social conditioning can overcome these tendencies. What’s hard-wired is only a predisposition to act in certain ways. B) The fact that a predisposition is hard-wired certainly does not imply that it is morally right. It implies only that in the past it tended to produce success in making new copies of the genes of the individuals who had it. Now let’s get to the meat. 3. The nature of moral principles. Quote:
Quote:
This isn’t rocket science. Blurring such fundamental distinctions is not conducive to clear thinking. Quote:
Quote:
This is not a trick or a verbal quibble. Morality deals with questions like “How shall I live” and “How shall I treat other people?” Answers to questions of this kind are necessarily of the form “Act in such-and-such a manner”. When one says “You ‘should’ act in such-and-such a manner” one is merely using a different grammatical form to answer the same kind of question. The use of this grammatical form is rather unfortunate, because it is often used to express propositions. And this has misled a great many people into thinking that moral statements of this kind also express propositions, when in fact they are recommending, advising, or approving the course of action in question. That doesn’t mean that the recommendation or advice embodied in a moral statement cannot be objectively valid. It makes perfectly good sense to say that a piece of advice or a recommendation can be objectively valid. For example, suppose you’re in Chicago and someone says, “I want to get to Texarkana. What shall I do?” The advice “Head south” is objectively valid (though incomplete), whereas the advice “Head north” is objectively invalid. (Of course, moral statement aren’t valid in this simple sense either.) 4. Morality and emotion Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
5. Deriving moral principles Quote:
Anyway, this is a side issue. The fact that certain kinds of behavior have evolved through natural selection tells us nothing about what moral principles are valid; it tells us only what behaviors promote the propagation of genes. Unless one starts with the premise that the propagation of one’s genes is the highest value, this tells us nothing about what behaviors are morally right. Quote:
Also, you cannot at the same time maintain that morality has a rational basis and that animals “display morality” by engaging in behavior based on “structures” that produce predispositions to that kind of behavior. For any kind of behavior to be meaningfully described both as “moral” and “rational”, it must not only be in accordance with valid moral principles, but must be done (at least partly) because it conforms to such principles. Behavior that springs from “building-block structures” that are connected with emotions doesn’t cut it. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Second, if all that empathy tells us is that other people basically feel as I do, how does that imply that I should try to get them what they want? Perhaps it implies that I should use the similarity of other people’s mental processes to mine to manipulate them into helping me as much as possible. You don’t seem to have grasped the gap between “is” and “ought”. Let me put the problem in yet another way. Empathy tells me that other people desire that they have a happy life, just as I desire that I have one. This is not really “feeling the same about many things”. What it would mean for someone else to feel the same as I do with respect to my desire to have a happy life would be that he would also desire that I lead a happy life. While such a desire does exist in many people, it is normally very weak compared to their desire to have a happy life themselves. To show that a happy life for me is intrinsically (i.e., objectively) good, and not merely good from my biased point of view, you need to show that other people have a rational reason to desire that I have a happy life. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
At this point you might want to read the exposition of my own ideas on the foundations of morality which start around the bottom of page 7 of this thread. The essence of my position is that people really do have the same basic goals and purposes at bottom, but this fact is obscured by a radical lack of knowledge and understanding. I believe (and give reasons for believing) that if everyone had enough knowledge and understanding they would regard my welfare as being equally as desirable as their own and act accordingly (and conversely, of course). This is a real foundation for morality. It implies that altruistic behavior is rational in the sense that it is how we would behave if we had enough K&U. And as I also argue, it is rational to pursue the goals that one would have if one had enough K&U (insofar as it is possible to know what they would be) and irrational not to. |
|||||||||||||||||||||
09-25-2002, 03:54 PM | #294 | ||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Quote:
1. Close the door. 2. Which way is Winchester? 3. A triangle is a polygon with three sides. 4. Let’s go to the movies tonight. 5. We’ve got to win this game. 6. Oh my gosh! It’s also possible, of course, for a statement to express nothing at all. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
|
||||||
09-25-2002, 03:57 PM | #295 | ||||||||||||||||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Longbow:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
(2) Assuming that you do not consider moral statements to be tautologies, what would constitute falsifying evidence? Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
My own position is that things like the Principle of Induction and Occam’s Razor are metaphysical axioms, and that metaphysical axioms are not propositions. (Actually calling them “axioms” is a bit misleading since, as explained earlier, I think they are properly formulated as principles of action.) For a more detailed explanation of this idea see the old thread <a href="http://iidb.org/cgi-bin/ultimatebb.cgi?ubb=get_topic&f=21&t=000384" target="_blank">On the nature of metaphysical axioms</a>. [ September 25, 2002: Message edited by: bd-from-kg ]</p> |
||||||||||||||||||||||
09-25-2002, 07:23 PM | #296 | |||||||||||||||||
Junior Member
Join Date: Sep 2002
Location: Milwaukee
Posts: 99
|
Quote:
Quote:
And if you want to know where this discussion is likely to end up, then, I think that the root of this view lies in the fact that philosophy is informal while math is formal. It will likely become my contention that you are basically reacting to this fact by doubting the legitimacy of philosophy as it is traditionally practiced. I will say that it is really just how big a role “philosophical vagueness” plays in the subject matter as to whether or not something is formal and that really does not affect its nature as being an analysis of propositions. I don’t know for sure that any of this will come to pass because it is hard to figure out where you stand exactly. But basically if you are a positivist or empiricist, then this is the likely direction the discussion will go in. (I’m trying to figure out how much of one you are…) Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
“Truth” as in a true proposition is not a physical object. It is part of “reality” in that one can formulate assertions about it. The whole subject of numbers being real is really the problem of universals. I am a conceptualist. I am not a nominalist who believes that numbers are names for classes of objects (e.g. 7 refers to the collection of all collections of 7 things, “blue refers to the collection of all blue things, and so on). I am not a realist who thinks that numbers “exist” like physical objects. However, I do think that statements about numbers can be true or false in the ordinary sense of the words which (I say) means that they are “real” and that statements about them express some aspect of “reality”. Quote:
Quote:
Furthermore, I will say that my moral philosophy is certainly disputable. Perhaps I have not really captured the relevant “definition” of “morality” in some cases. That doesn’t mean there isn’t one, and we must generally assume there is. But, without further adieu, I have a deontological moral world view that is not too different from the Kantian idea of respect. It is my contention that the principle of universalizability alone gives us an objective notion of “justice”. (When I speak of the principle of universalizability, I am referring to what is often called a “thin” concept of morality with it as opposed to some of the thicker notions that Kant, for instance, might suggest.) Perhaps a general way of characterizing my views as to say that morality is basically about impartiality. It’s not that different from a Kantian view, but I would hate to besmirch his name with my views. Quote:
For instance, in the classic example of a synthetic a priori proposition: “I think”, I used to say that it is really analytic because “think” is actually contained in “I”. But then, it is often retorted, things like “Will you be thinking when you’re dead,” or “Do you cease to exist when you stop thinking,” that sort of thing. Then, perhaps that I am thinking is not contained in the “I”, but is instead a necessary fact if I am considering the proposition “I think”. Perhaps you will say that you observe that you are thinking when you are thinking about “I think”. Whether that is true or not, I think you can know that you must be a priori, so I do think that “I think” is a priori true. Anyway, this sort of thing could digress into a huge discussion that is actually probably not that relevant to my view but maybe more central to yours. What is more important is that morality is a priori. I think that the reason the whole synthetic/analytic dichotomy can become important is if you actually make the criticism that moral statements cannot be analytic and so cannot be a priori. Quote:
Quote:
This probably goes back to the lack of formality, I think. Is it the lack of a precise definition that you have a problem with? Is that why you are saying that these topics have no propositional content? Quote:
For instance, the whole discussion about what “reality” is presumably has some relation to common issues about reality. You cannot just be speaking your own private language to yourself. Otherwise, nothing you say is relevant to what I say and unbeknownst to me, everything I am saying is non sequitur to what you are saying. Ultimately it comes down to what you really mean and how that relates to what other people mean when they talk about the same subjects. So, using your own terminology is one thing, but on some level we have to be talking about the same thing. So, much like applying Ockham’s Razor, you must come up with the most faithful interpretation of the topic. It is similar to interpreting the law. Often the law is inconsistent, so the idea is to come up with the most consistent interpretation of the law that is as faithful as possible to the legislators’ intent. It is the same with all of these: interpreting language, interpreting the law, interpreting evidence. If you start to add gratuitous propositions, then you are begging the question on those extra assertions. There is no particular reason to believe them. If our interpretation of everything results in a bigger violation of the relevant usage than mine does, we must reject yours in favor of mine. Quote:
[ September 25, 2002: Message edited by: Longbow ] [ September 25, 2002: Message edited by: Longbow ]</p> |
|||||||||||||||||
09-28-2002, 12:49 PM | #297 | ||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Longbow:
I’m afraid that this post is a bit on the long side. The issues that you raised are pretty fundamental and I haven’t discussed some of them before. Hopefully after this we’ll be able to zero in on the important issues that we actually disagree about. 1. What are we talking about? Ultimately what we’re talking about here is the meaning of moral language – e.g., what it means to say “X should do Y”. But we immediately come up against the problem that there is no such thing as an “objectively correct” meaning of a word or phrase; there is only “how it is used”. Anyone can define “should” to mean whatever he likes, but if we want to use words to communicate it is advisable to try to use them in ways that correspond to the way other people use them. Thus if we want to discuss something that most people would recognize as “morality” we are not free to simply make up any definitions we please; we must pay attention to common usage. As you say: Quote:
An example of the kind of problem that can arise in trying to use language in ways that correspond to ordinary usage can be seen in common statements about the sun’s relationship to the earth. Thus it is often said (in fact we’ve all said it lots of times) that the sun is going to “rise” or “set” at such-and-such a time, or that the sun “rises” in the east. Today we know that this language is technically incorrect, but let’s imagine that we are living around 5000 B.C. and happen to know the true state of affairs, but that the vast majority of people believe that the sun really goes around the earth. We might therefore propose to interpret statements to the effect that the sun will “rise” at a certain time as meaning that it will be below the horizon shortly before that time and above it shortly afterward. But at this point Smith might object that this will not do, because this interpretation clearly does not “square with common usage”. We might then explain to him the true state of affairs. At this point Smith might argue that, given that the sun does not go around the earth, the ordinary way of speaking is simply meaningless, and that it is pointless to try to “interpret” it at all. At this point we might reasonably say that, although this language is based on a mistaken conception of “the way things are” it is nevertheless meaningful; it refers to a reality about the world. Thus if someone says that the sun is going to rise tomorrow at such-and-such a time, it is more sensible to interpret this as a statement about when the sun will be above the horizon rather than to dismiss it out of hand as meaningless. In the kind of issues dealt with by philosophy, ordinary usage is often meaningless in a similar way, except that the meaninglessness arises from conceptual confusion rather than erroneous beliefs about the “real world”. For example, people often say that someone acted “of his own free will”. If they are asked what they mean by this they will generally give an account that is clearly incompatible with determinism – i.e., they are referring to what is often called “libertarian” or “metaphysical” free will. But careful analysis shows that this concept is logically incoherent. Yet when people say that a person acted “freely” they are clearly referring to something significant. It matters whether a person acted freely or not; it is morally significant whether the circumstances were such that an agent would generally be said to have acted of his own free will. The task of the philosopher is to discover just what this difference really consists of and explain why it matters – why it is a morally significant difference. So yes, if one wants to be “relevant”, one must “square” one’s interpretation with common usage. But as these examples illustrate, what it means to square an interpretation with common usage is not entirely straightforward. It certainly does not consist of asking people what they “mean” and accepting that as the correct interpretation. It means analyzing how the relevant language is actually used and finding a consistent, meaningful interpretation that is as consistent as possible with this usage. If common usage is based (as it often is) on misconceptions and logical confusions, no interpretation can be completely consistent with common usage. Sometimes it’s not clear which of two or more interpretations are “most consistent”, or at any rate it’s a pretty close call. In such cases it is legitimate to consider factors such as simplicity, usefulness, and fecundity. 2. On the burden of proof In response to my question of what’s wrong with deciding that some statements that appear to express propositions really don’t, you said: Quote:
Quote:
3. On what “exists” and what is “real”. Applying the “common usage” criterion to the question of what “exists” is straightforward in cases like snails, trees, yeti, aliens from Arcturus, or unicorns; we all understand what it means to say that such things exist. Beyond that, things get murkier. Some people apparently deny that emotions exist. Some question whether the past can properly be said to exist. So it’s not surprising that there is disagreement about whether the natural numbers can be said to exist. In all of these cases the problem with taking common usage as a guide is that we are taking the term beyond its original domain where the meaning is clear and straightforward, and trying to apply it to more “fuzzy” areas where there is no clear consensus. At this point considerations of consistency and utility come into play. The same kind of problem appears in trying to interpret what it means to say that something is real, or “part of reality”. Some people take the position that saying that something is “real” or “part of reality” means the same thing as saying that it “exists”. You prefer to make a distinction. And on this point I agree with you. Thus, the relationship between me and the chair I’m sitting on does not “exist”, but it is “real” or “part of reality”. This corresponds much better to the way such words are normally used. As you may recall, I accepted your definition of “reality” with one modification. Instead of saying that “reality” is "that which is represented by all true propositions" I suggested defining it as “that which is represented by all propositions which are true in this world, but not in all possible worlds.” This easily includes things such as the relationship between me and my chair; in other words it admits a great number of things as “real” which cannot properly be said to “exist”. In fact, on reflection I’m not at all sure that there is any substantive difference between your definition and mine. The only difference in the definitions themselves is that mine excludes tautologies. But tautologies cannot properly be said to “represent” anything, so excluding them does not exclude anything from “reality” that would be included by your definition. But I gather that you don’t agree that analytic statements don’t “refer” to anything. Specifically, you point out that they refer to numbers. Thus: Quote:
4. On “synthetic a priori” propositions It seems that you are determined to say that moral statements express propositions. but since (unlike many of the people in this forum) you recognize that they cannot be expressing either analytic or empirical propositions, you are forced to say that they express some other kind of proposition. But it’s hard to see what other kind of proposition there could be, because analytic and empirical propositions between them seem to cover all of the logical possibilities. To see this, suppose that a proposition is not analytic (or self-contradictory). Thus there are logically possible worlds in which it is true and other logically possible worlds in which it is false. So in order to determine whether this world is in the first category or the second we need information about it. In other words, we need evidence. But to say that it cannot be determined whether a proposition is true or false without looking at evidence is to say that it is empirical. In spite of this seemingly airtight argument you say that there is another category of propositions, which (following Kant) you call “synthetic a priori” propositions. By an “a priori” proposition you mean one whose truth can be determined independent of any evidence. but a synthetic proposition is one that entails actual information about the world – i.e., that something is true which is not a tautology. You explain this idea as follows: Quote:
It seems to me that a much better definition is the one used in formal logic: a statement is analytic if it is logically impossible for it to be false. Or equivalently, it is analytic if there is no model in which it is false. (The equivalence of these definitions is guaranteed by Godel’s completeness theorem.) But this is exactly your definition of “a priori” propositions. Another perfectly good definition of an analytic proposition is that it is one whose truth is entailed by the meanings of the terms involved. But you seem to consider this as well to be a defining characteristic of “synthetic a priori” propositions: Quote:
These comments seem to get us nowhere in terms of understanding how there could be a proposition which entails real information about the world but which can be known to be true without evidence. So let’s turn to your alleged examples: Occam’s Razor and “I exist”. A) Occam’s Razor As I pointed out earlier, it is impossible to say what it is that Occam’s Razor supposedly asserts. This isn’t just a matter of being “fuzzy”: it’s impossible to specify any statement about the real world that it entails. For example, it does not say that a simpler hypothesis is more likely to be true than a more complicated one. In fact, it’s impossible to say what it means say that one scientific hypothesis is “more likely to be true” than another. (In fact, it’s impossible even to say what it means to say that a scientific hypothesis is true.) What is says is that the simpler hypothesis is to be preferred to the more complicated one. But this is not a statement of fact; it is more in the nature of a recommendation It’s also impossible to say what it means to say that it’s “true”. In other words, it seems to me that Occam’s Razor would be equally valid in any possible world, which means that it says nothing about the nature of the world. I gather that your answer to this would be that the mere fact that Occam’s Razor is a valid principle in all possible worlds doesn’t mean that it says nothing about the nature of the world. But try as I might, I can’t make any sense out of this notion. If an alleged proposition does not “divide” possible worlds into two nonempty classes - those in which it is true and those in which it is false - it is empty: it has no informational content. But the only true empty propositions are analytic ones - i.e., tautologies. And tautologies are true merely by virtue of the meaning of the terms that appear in them, so they say nothing about the nature of the world. B) “I think” Unlike Occam’s Razor, it’s clear enough what “I think” means, even though its meaning is basically impossible to define. (It’s inevitable that the process of defining concepts in terms of simpler ones must eventually terminate in concepts that are absolutely basic – they cannot be defined in terms of anything simpler still. But that doesn’t mean that such concepts are meaningless; otherwise we would have to conclude that all concepts are meaningless. In the case of “I think” we seem to be dealing with two absolutely basic concepts: “I” and “think”.) It’s also clear that it’s possible for it to be false in the sense that there are logically possible worlds in which it is false. Finally, it’s clear (or at least it seems to be) that I don’t have to look around for evidence that i exist; I “just know”. So have we arrived at last at a “synthetic a priori” proposition? Not really. It just seems that way because it’s a conclusion I reached so long ago that I can’t remember doing so, or the process by which I reached the conclusion. Indeed, my mind was in such a primitive state at the time that it’s something of a stretch even to say that I “concluded” that I exist, and the process involved had nothing to do with “reason” as it is normally understood. But this is true of many other “conclusions” that I reached around that time. The most important and relevant of these was that there is an “external world” or external reality. Now the process by which I “concluded” that I exist and the one by which I “concluded” that there is an external world were actually the same process. The realization slowly dawned that some of the things perceived could be manipulated or controlled by an “act of will”, while others couldn’t. (Later it was learned that these things were parts of what was called my “body”.) Much later it was found to be a productive explanatory hypothesis that the things that could not be controlled directly included objects that appeared to “control” their own movements. And still later the realization dawned that some experiences (such as seeing trees, chairs, etc.) were shared by these “self-controlled” objects, while others (like pain, anger, likes and dislikes, memories) were not – or at least, not with any consistency. Eventually the things that could be controlled directly and the aspects of experiences that were not shared by self-controlled objects came to be thought of as “me”; the former constituted my “physical” self and the latter my “mental” self or consciousness. At a very early stage this became such a fundamental, essential part of the conceptual framework that was developed to make sense of experiences that it came to seem “self-evident”. No conceivable evidence, it seemed, could shake the conviction that there is an “I” – a “self” – who is having these experiences, distinct from the experiences themselves. But in fact this belief is based on evidence: the evidence of my earliest experiences. But that’s not the end of the story. One of the most striking conclusions that seems to be arising from the rapidly developing science of consciousness is that there really is no “I” – that the “self” is an illusion. I don’t want to get into this in detail here. The point is that the fact that this question can even be asked shows that “I exist” is indeed an empirical hypothesis, and that it might conceivably be false. Whether it’s true will ultimately be decided by the evidence. So this is very far from being an a priori proposition. This shouldn’t be too surprising. Many of the things that Kant proposed as “synthetic a priori” truths have turned out to be either ordinary empirical propositions which in fact are false, or analytic propositions. The theorems of Euclidian geometry are a good case in point. Kant thought that these were clearly “synthetic a priori truths”. But it is now clear that this was a mistake. Taken in one way, Euclid’s theorems are analytic truths: his system can be rigorously axiomatized, and the theorems can be shown to follow logically from the axioms. But the axioms can also be interpreted as assertions about physical reality, and when taken in this way they are false. Either way they are not “synthetic a priori” truths. 5. Your moral theory So far you haven’t said much about your own moral theory. What you have said is this: Quote:
i) Certainly any “reasonable” theory of morality has to involve impartiality. But as has often been noted, this concept can hardly be “all there is to it”. One can impartially consign everyone (including oneself) to eternal torment, or make everyone incredibly happy but stark raving mad, or ... but you get the idea. In addition to impartiality there has to be at least one positive principle. This seems to lead unavoidably to the idea of an “intrinsically good” state of affairs. And as soon as actions are judged “right” or “wrong” at least partly on the basis of whether they tend to lead to or produce such a state of affairs, one no longer has a purely deontological theory; it is at least partly consequentialist or teleological. ii) This is all rather vague at this point. you haven’t offered an actual statement which supposedly expresses one of those “synthetic a priori” moral propositions that you’ve talked so much about. And this gets you off the hook (for the moment) in terms of explaining just how we can know without evidence of any kind that such a proposition is true. iii) Finally, there is a problem inherent in all moral theories that try to interpret moral statements as expressing propositions. How do you get from “You should do X” to “Do X”? The first (in your interpretation) is simply a declarative sentence, like “Grass is green”, while the second is an imperative or injunction. To put it another way, the question “Why be good?” is unanswerable in terms of your theory. It yields no motive or purpose for “doing the right thing”; all that it does (at best) is to identify what “the right thing” is. 6. My moral theory I think that you have some basic misconceptions about my theory. For example, you say: Quote:
My position is that some moral statements are like Occam’s Razor in that they can be derived from principles of action that a sufficiently rational person with enough knowledge and understanding will recognize as valid. When people say that a moral statement is “true” they really mean that it is in this category. (but only in the same sense in which, when someone who believes that the sun goes around the earth says that the sun is going to rise tomorrow morning, he “really” means that it will appear above the horizon for the first time in several hours.) But ordinarily when we say that a declarative statement is “true” we mean something quite different, namely that it expresses a true proposition. And as we have seen, true propositions come in only two flavors: analytic and empirical. Analytic propositions are tautologies, while empirical ones say something about the “real world” – that is, there are logically possible worlds in which they are false. It seems clear that moral statements are neither analytic nor empirical, so they cannot be properly said to express propositions. This has led some, like the logical positivists, to dismiss them as meaningless or as merely expressions of emotions or attitudes. But this is as wrongheaded as saying that Occam’s Razor is meaningless or merely an expression of an emotion or attitude. This kind of misunderstanding arises from trying to analyze moral statements as expressing propositions. Once we recognize that they actually express of principles of action (or things that can be derived from such principles) this difficulty vanishes and the way is open for interpreting them as meaningful and (in some cases) universally valid. 7. The relationship between our theories Actually we are not as far apart in our views of morality as might at first appear. You say that valid moral principles are synthetic a priori propositions; I prefer, for technical reasons, to say that they are not propositions at all but valid principles of action that any sufficiently rational person with enough knowledge and understanding will recognize as such. The similarities here are obvious. In both cases we say that moral principles cannot be derived or proved from facts about the world, but that nevertheless a sufficiently rational person with enough understanding should be able to “just see” that they are valid. [ September 28, 2002: Message edited by: bd-from-kg ]</p> |
||||||||
09-28-2002, 08:32 PM | #298 | ||||||||||||||||||||||
Junior Member
Join Date: Sep 2002
Location: Milwaukee
Posts: 99
|
Quote:
Quote:
Also, if you have a precise interpretation while others are informal and imprecise, then I do not think that gives your interpretation any more credibility (necessarily). Ultimately, a big part of the problem of understanding morality is to correctly identify the concepts. As part and parcel with understanding the true nature of moral concepts, you will always have to quarrel over the relevance of the concepts you imagine to those that most people are alluding to when they make moral statements. All-in-all, it's a big philosophical issue that cannot be easily averted. Quote:
I also think that the term "unicorn" refers to a concept and that it is more than just an arbitrary part of the definition of the term that such a concept includes the aspect of having one horn. Even if you went to a land where everyone used the term "unicorn" to refer to some other thing, there would still exist the concept of essentially a one horned horse. And, you could say to yourself and others that such a thing does not exist Quote:
Quote:
In any case, the sentence you are coming up with is either true "by definition" or it isn't. If you are going to say that there is more to its truth than just the definition of "truth", then you are, in a very profound way, endorsing the possibility of what philosophers often characterize as "the synthetic a priori". And for that matter, if you think the definition of "truth" is not arbitrary, I would argue that you have to accept such a possibility. So, the question back to you, then is how would you prove that such a statement as you give is true? Would you go back to the three formal laws fo logic and leave it at that? Suppose that someone questions the veracity of those laws? What then? Would you argue a case beyond that or would you just stop talking to them? If you just stop talking, then perhaps you can accept that the statement is true by the definition of "true". If you think that you can say things like "it wouldn't make sense of being meaningful to say otherwise," then it seems to me that you are implicitly accepting what Kant would say is the synthetic a priori. What you are doing is sort of "backing into" the truth of some proposition informally by determining that it is essential to the enterprise you are already engaging in. That makes it not just a derivative of some arbitrary definition you have come up with but a much more profound statement about "the way things are." Quote:
The main reason I asked you if you thought math was analytic was not to ask you if you thought it was a priori. What I am driving at might be almost characterized as asking you if you are a Logical Positivist. There is a distinction, I think, among logical positivists between the terms or otherwise saying something like that their position is characterized by the rejection of the possibility of a synthetic a priori proposition wouldn't really be all that meaningful. And this is exactly the sort of thing I think one of them said, for instance. (I am too lazy to get the quote, but I think it was Carnap that said it.) In any case, the real issue lies in "how true", for instance, you think the laws of logic, say, are. If you think that they are just an arbitrary construct, then I think you are much more in line with the outlook of positivism and empiricism. If you think that there is more to it than that -- that it is nonsense to question them -- then I think you are starting to digress from such a view. That has been a problem for quite sometime in the history of philosophy. Empiricism is so intuitively appealing, but it has this problem of philosophical skepticism that plagues it. Hume was certainly plagued by it and, I think, that everyone runs into a variation of the "skeptics paradox". The positivists have the criticism of verifying the principle of verification. Wittgenstein talks about his philosophy in the Tractatus as being a ladder that you use to climb out of such considerations with and then discard. The approach has always been to bootstrap your way into it, and I don't think you can do that in philosophy. Instead you need to create a foundation that everything rests on, so if there is a point where things are coming out of thin air, then that is your foundation: thin air. Quote:
The direction you are headed is to do away with propositions and replace them with sentences. You are not going to say anymore that: 2+2=4. Instead you will say: "2+2=4" is "true". Of course that statement, itself, is conceptual, so we are back to the issue of philosophical skepticism. (I am fairly certain you will contest this paragraph, but I am not sure in what way.) Quote:
And, incidentally, I think it sounds like you wuold say a similar thing since you say that these analytic truths are so because they are true in all possible worlds. It sounds like you are saying they are universally true. Perhaps, you just mean that you find it expedient to assume them independently of the world you happen to be in. Quote:
That should indicate that such a discussion is irrelevant to the proposition "I exist." Perhaps you had the belief before you even knew what a "belief" was, but that doesn't mean that know that you do know what a belief is, you cannot go back and figure out how you know that you exist. Now, we certainly are well-developed minds that can know that "I exist". This proposition seems true -- why? Not why does it seem true or why do we believe it to be true -- why is it true? Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
In any case, you have said that impartiality is essential to morality. Is that a "recommendation"? It sounds like an assertion about the nature of morality. And it doesn't sound like you are saying that everyone is creatign impartial moralities (which isn't even the case). Quote:
Identifying what the "right thing" is is all a moral philosophy has to do. What I think you are refering to is the question of obligation: "Why should I be moral?" It is easy to construe this "should" as not in a specific moral sense but in a more general sense. The truth is that it only means that morality must apply to everyone equally. The other question of why I should (rationally speaking) find that it is the moral thing to do be a persuasive argument for doing it is actually not essential to moral dilemmas. (Again, this about squaring up our metaethical views to common usage of ethical terms.) Quote:
You actually see this sort of thing. I might change word order to emphasize something or I might add honorifics to convey respect. The couching of an imperative statement in the form of a declarative sentence is just an extreme version of that sort of thing, so Stevenson seems to suggest. Of course, I disagree with this characterization of moral statements, arguing that it doesn't adequately capture the usage. And, I claim to have a better interpretation anyway. Quote:
If you believe something in a way that is inconsistent with Ockham's Razor then you don't really know what you claim to. Quote:
Sometimes I get the impression that you just say that as a matter of definition -- that there is no real difference between such subjects and any other subject of inquiry, but that strictly speaking they are not subjects involving propositions. Other times it sounds like there might be a more profound aspect of them not being about propositions than just semantics. What is the real difference between a subject like epistemology and functional analysis? Of course there are some differences, but I wonder what you consider to be the real meanignful ones. Quote:
Beyond that, the Logical Positiists are certainly very vocal about moral and political philosophy. Basically, they were Marxist, I think, as any good philosopher was at the turn of the Century. And, there were several papers on things like how Marxism was a paradigm of scientificly approaching ethics and how this is how ethics should be handled and so on. So, it isn't what it may sound like: a dismissal of all moral discourse. I think that is the problem -- it should be, but it isn't. And I think that your view should be, too, but somehow isn't. You have trouble wrapping your hands aroudn the possibility of a syntehtic a priori proposition. I have trouble wrapping my hands around how your views on any philosophical matter could possibly be compelling or persuasive. What does it mean that Ockham's razor is "a recommendation"? Then its not true? What are the consequences for rejecting it? Why does it matter at all, intellectually speaking? And more generally, are you saying that science isn't "true"? You can't be, right -- you are saying that it consists of propositions. But is that statement -- that science consists of propositions -- "true"? We're back to the "skeptics paradox". That statement seems to me to be a metaphysical or perhaps epistemological one. Okay, that philosophy does not consist of propositions -- is that a proposition? It has to be. But it is a philosophical statement. Perhaps some philosophical statements are propositions and others aren't since after all you haven't really said that all of philosophy lacks propositional content. Then what's the difference between things like saying that Ockham's Razor is essential to proper justification (which is essential to knowledge) and other philosophical statements? They are all informal, if that's the problem. They are all extremely foundational, if that's the problem. Quote:
The problem with your view is that it lacks veracity. (Of course!) What I mean by that is that the statements in it are not compelling. They do not have the veracity of a "true statement". Yet, you seem to think they are as compelling without being "true". Quote:
Perhaps my views are the same... |
||||||||||||||||||||||
10-03-2002, 11:10 AM | #299 | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Longbow:
Since your last post was so long and my time lately has been short, I still haven’t been able to put together a full reply to it. But here’s a response to the first part - i.e., the part before you get around to discussing morality proper. I hope to get the rest done sometime tomorrow. It’s not clear that we have any real disagreements on the first two points, so let’s proceed directly to the third. 3. On what “exists” and what is “real”. Quote:
Quote:
4. On “synthetic a priori” propositions Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
First, you’re analyzing a different statement than the one I proposed. “X is true” may mean the same thing as “X” in the sense that the one is true if and only if the other is, but they aren’t the same statement. If you want to show that it makes sense to say that an analytic statement is one whose predicate is contained in its subject, you have to show that the predicate of the original statement is contained in its subject, not that the predicate of some other statement is. Second, you can’t just redefine the subject as the predicate and the predicate as the subject. If I asked you what were the subject and predicate of the sentence “Grass is green”, you wouldn’t say (contrary to all the rules of grammar) that the subject is “green” and the predicate is “grass”. “Grass” is a noun; “green” is an adjective. “Greenness” is the property being predicated of grass; “grassness” is not being predicated of green. In the same way, the sentence “‘Either (A and B), or not-A, or not-B' is true" is predicating the property of truth to the sentence ‘Either (A and B), or not-A, or not-B'; it is not predicating the property of ‘Either (A and B), or not-A, or not-B'-ness to “true”. Finally, if this is the correct analysis of my sentence, it’s the correct analysis of any sentence. Thus, if I were to ask what are the subject and predicate of the sentence “This beach ball is big”, according to your analysis the correct answer is: “Strictly speaking the statement is “ ‘This beach ball is big’ is true.’ And the predicate is actually what appears to be the subject. Thus the subject is “true” and the predicate is “This beach ball is big”. I can assure you that this answer would earn you an “F” in any English class in the country. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
For example, why is it “true” that “If A implies B and A, then B” ? Because that’s what “implies means. Why is it true that “If A and B, then A”? Because that’s what “and” means. (Or rather, it’s half of what it means, the other half being “If A and B, then B”.) Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
This is the solution to some “skeptic’s paradox” problems – to note that some things that appear at first sight to be assertions about the “real world” for which there cannot, even in principle, be any evidence, are really disguised definitions. The other main strategy is the one you’re already familiar with – by saying that things like the Principle of Induction, Occam’s Razor are properly formulated as principles of rational action. Quote:
In particular, let A consist only of the axioms of logic, and suppose that Occam’s Razor actually expresses a proposition – call it OR. If OR is true in all models of A (i.e., if it is true in all possible worlds) by the Completeness Theorem it can be proved from A. But the only things that can be proved from A are tautologies – i.e., analytic statements. This follows directly from the fact that A consists entirely of definitions. Or if you want to quarrel with this, at any rate it consists entirely of propositions which are true by virtue of the meaning of the terms that occur in them. But clearly the only sorts of things that can be proved from such propositions are other propositions that are true by virtue of the meaning of the terms in them – i.e., analytic propositions. And it is clear that OR is not an analytic proposition. Therefore it is not true in all models of A – i.e., it is not a valid principle in all possible worlds. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
The reason for this “historical” approach was to explain how it can seem that my knowledge that I exist is a priori even thought it’s actually based on evidence. Actually we have a great many justified beliefs about the “real world” that were not the product of a series of rational inferences from the evidence. The human mind doesn’t typically work that was. What matters is that the processes leading to these beliefs can be rationally reconstructed in this form. If all of the beliefs that we formed this way, including all of the beliefs about the “real world” formed in childhood, were considered “unjustified” because they were not the product of rational inferences, we would have virtually no justified true beliefs at all. Note: You may prefer to say that the kinds of beliefs that I’m talking about really were the product of a series of rational inferences, but that they just weren’t conscious inferences. I have no problem with that. One can argue that even a baby is thinking “rationally”, but is just unable to put this rational thought in the form of words. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
At any rate, when Kant says that "the quantity of matter is always preserved" is a synthetic a priori claim, he is clearly saying that scientific hypotheses – things that are obviously not true in all possible worlds – can be known independently of evidence. I say that this is crapola. [ October 03, 2002: Message edited by: bd-from-kg ]</p> |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
10-03-2002, 03:52 PM | #300 | ||||||||||||||||||||
Junior Member
Join Date: Sep 2002
Location: Milwaukee
Posts: 99
|
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
<a href="http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Mathematicians/Godel.html" target="_blank">http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Mathematicians/Godel.html</a> In particular: "He is best known for his proof of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems. In 1931 he published these results in Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme . He proved fundamental results about axiomatic systems showing in any axiomatic mathematical system there are propositions that cannot be proved or disproved within the axioms of the system. In particular the consistency of the axioms cannot be proved. This ended a hundred years of attempts to establish axioms to put the whole of mathematics on an axiomatic basis. One major attempt had been by Bertrand Russell with Principia Mathematica (1910-13). Another was Hilbert's formalism which was dealt a severe blow by Gödel's results. The theorem did not destroy the fundamental idea of formalism, but it did demonstrate that any system would have to be more comprehensive than that envisaged by Hilbert's. " So, the point, then, is that I think the common view is that Godel not only completely refuted Logicism, but practically did as much to Formalism. I think that the idea that one could formally derive all that is true in math from formal axioms is generally rejected. And, certainly, the Principia is not an example of the formalization of mathematics. Quote:
Quote:
Also, you cannot just present formal symbols arbitrarily as if they were always meaningful. There is an informal sentence -- a complete sentence -- that your string of symbols corresponds to whcih is clearly what the characterization "the subject contains the predicate" refers to. In other words, rewrite the formal expression of symbols you presented as a complete sentence using no symbols. Furthermore, you must take such a complex sentence and reduce it to a form where you can easily get the atomic propositions out of it. Then, if you can prove that there is still no sense in which "the subject is contained in the predicate" you will have shown that such a characterization is meaningless (at least in that case). Quote:
It might seem like "truth value" is derived from the character of the logic. And I suppose it is in the sense that "truth value" just refers to whatever can be derived with that logic. But, if we are trying to contend that this is actually relevant to the way we think, then the issue is whether or not that notion of what it means to make an assertion corresponds to what people are trying to do when they make assertions. In other words, it boils down to what it means to claim something is true. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
-- The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Mathematicians/Godel.html) Actually, there is a quote by Carnap, I think, to this effect. I just don't know where it is right now. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
In any case, I don't think this development of how we came to believe that we exist -- basically because we were created with it -- is an explanation of how such a belief is a posteriori. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Secondly, I agree with Kant that some amount of our contentions about the physical world are a priori. I do not believe that there are possible worlds in which they are false if they are indeed synthetic a priori. Right now, our current scientific models seem to have plenty of a priori assumptions underpinning them. These assumptions are what makes science a legitimate pursuit of knowledge. Without them, it would be really difficult to interpret what a theory might mean. And I am quite certain these assumptions about how to properly handle the physical world, what constitutes experimentally establishing an empirical fact, and so on does not follow formally from first order propositional logic. The extent to which Kant really defended the falsified assertions that are attributed to him is at least somewhat debatable. They are little more than passing remarks, and I don't think they are really crucial, personally, to the points he is usually trying to make in the Critique of Pure Reason. They certainly are at best only marginally related to the problem he is trying to solve. So, for instance, even if he is wrong about the parallel postulate, it is not clear that he is wrong about the epistemological nature of geometry in general. In fact, I don't think he is. |
||||||||||||||||||||
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|