FRDB Archives

Freethought & Rationalism Archive

The archives are read only.


Go Back   FRDB Archives > Archives > IIDB ARCHIVE: 200X-2003, PD 2007 > IIDB Philosophical Forums (PRIOR TO JUN-2003)
Welcome, Peter Kirby.
You last visited: Yesterday at 05:55 AM

 
 
Thread Tools Search this Thread
Old 06-20-2003, 01:38 PM   #101
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: Greensboro, NC, U.S.A.
Posts: 2,597
Default Well...

Quote:
Originally posted by bd-from-kg
Yes, but the consensus that’s needed is a consensus about what we want the system of justice to do; what the criterion is for comparing one system to another.
Don't you think it's also reasonable that we might want a consensus on how a system of justice does that which we want it to do as well?

IMO, that's really more to the point that The AntiChris is raising. Torture might be an extremely effective method of getting what we want out of a system of justice, but do those ends justify the means? To put it into the terms of your desideratum, as you say, torture may enable a regime to provide the greatest good for the greatest number, but is that the only consideration we would ever want to make? Don't we have a right to be concerned over the means as well as the end?

Don't we really need to answer that question with every form of punishment we establish? Not just what we want as a result, but how we want to get there?

Regards,

Bill Snedden
Bill Snedden is offline  
Old 06-20-2003, 05:13 PM   #102
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
Default

Mike Rosoft:

Quote:
To deny a chance of release to a criminal who can be reformed is to deny justice; to release a criminal who hasn't been reformed is to endanger the society.
To see what’s wrong with your statements, I’ll examine the second one first. I take it that your point is that since an unreformed criminal is (usually) a danger to society, such criminals should not be released. (Otherwise I don’t see what your point could possibly be.) But let’s look at a concrete case. Brown was convicted of stealing cars. The maximum sentence for this is (let’s say) ten year in prison. The ten years are now up, and Brown has been a model prisoner. But a “reform verification” board has determined that Brown probably hasn’t reformed: it’s likely that he’ll steal a car again if he’s released. So they decide to keep him in prison until he has reformed.

The problem here is that Brown is no longer being kept in prison as a punishment for what he has done, but strictly to prevent him from doing what the reform board fears he otherwise will do. But this is manifestly unjust. How is this different from simply locking someone up who’s never committed any crime because a psychological evaluation has determined that he’s likely to commit crimes in the future? (Shades of Minority Report!)

What this example shows is that, if we’re interested in justice, locking people up cannot be justified on the basis of what they are or are not likely to do in the future; it must be based on what they have done in the past.

Now let’s turn to your first statement, and consider the case of a criminal who can be reformed. Heck, forget about “can be”; let’s look at a prisoner who unquestionably has reformed. Two years ago Applebee kidnapped a young girl, abused her sexually in unspeakable ways, tortured her, and killed her. He was convicted a year ago and sentenced to life. but now he’s a changed man. Everyone agrees that he’s genuinely remorseful about what he did; that he’s wracked with guilt over it. Moreover, he’s now know as a man of the utmost integrity and even moral wisdom. His concern for the welfare of all of the other prisoners if manifest, and no one has the slightest doubt that it’s real. Should he be released on the grounds that he’s no longer a danger to society? I’m afraid not. He’s barely begun to pay the [price for what he did. Just as in Brown’s case, we cannot base the decision as to whether to release him on what he’s likely to do in the future; it must be based on what he did in the past.

Quote:
Seriously, do you suggest that [AI] ought to spend time and money to overturn convictions of people who have already been put to death?
Who said anything about overturning convictions? I say only that they have the time and opportunity to make their case.

Quote:
Aren't they better spent on someone who can be helped?
Proving that innocent people have been executed does help those who are now on death row. If they can come up with a significant number of such cases, it will almost certainly lead to the abolition of capital punishment. Don’t you think they know that?

Quote:
Do I have to comment on this baseless accusation?
Oh, please. Obviously this wasn’t an accusation. the point is that AI has lots of time to review cases of people who have been executed and try to prove that some of them were innocent; it’s not as though they’re trying to mount a revolution, which would take every ounce of energy they have available. Their claim that they just don’t have time for this is disingenuous.

Quote:
bd:
It’s beyond understanding why AI thinks that new cases of this kind will miraculously come to light as a result of abolishing the DP.

MR:
Just like they "miraculously" came into light after death penalty was abolished in United Kingdom.
Perhaps you can show me the connection between Britain’s abolishing CP and the discovery that at least one innocent person was executed. Are you saying that this wouldn’t have happened if Britain had retained CP? If so, on what grounds?

Quote:
After a short search on Internet, I found out where this number [about twenty innocent people were executed during the past 100 years] is from. It is a study by Hugo Bedau and Michael Radelet, named "Miscarriages of Justice in Potentially Capital Cases".
Ah, yes. This is a famous (or notorious) study. Since you seem to attach so much importance to the possibility of executing innocents, I’m going to discuss it at length.

First, here are some comments from Dudley Sharp of Justice for All:

Quote:
The most significant study conducted to evaluate the evidence of the "innocent executed" is the Bedau-Radelet Study ("Miscarriages of Justice in Potentially Capital Cases," 40, 1 Stanford Law Review, 11/87). The study concluded that 23 innocent persons had been executed since 1900. However, the study's methodology was so flawed that at least 12 of those cases had no evidence of innocence and substantial evidence of guilt. Bedau & Radelet, both opponents, "consistently presented incomplete and misleading accounts of the evidence." (Markman, Stephen J. & Cassell, Paul G., "Protecting the Innocent: A Response to the Bedau-Radelet Study" 41, 1 Stanford Law Review, 11/88). The remaining 11 cases represent 0.14% of the 7,800 executions which have taken place since 1900. And, there is, in fact, no proof that those 11 executed were innocent. In addition, the "innocents executed" group was extracted from a Bedau & Radelet imagined pool of 350 persons who were, supposedly, wrongly convicted of capital or "potentially" capital crimes. Not only were they at least 50% in error with their 23 "innocents executed" claim, but 211 of those 350 cases, or 60%, were not sentenced to death. Bedau and Radelet already knew that plea bargains, the juries, the evidence, the prosecutors, judicial review and/or the legal statutes had put these crimes in the "no capital punishment" category. Indeed, their claims of innocence, regarding the remaining 139 of those 350 cases, should be suspect, given this study’s poor level of accuracy. Calling their work misleading hardly does this "academic" study justice. Had a high school student presented such a report, where 50-60% of the material was either false or misleading, a grade of F would be a likely result.

Indeed, Michigan Court of Appeals Judge Stephen Markman finds that " . . . the Bedau-Radelet study is remarkable not (as retired Supreme Court Judge Harry Blackmun seems to believe) for demonstrating that mistakes involving the death penalty are common, but rather for demonstrating how uncommon they are . . . This study - the most thorough and painstaking analysis ever on the subject - fails to prove that a single such mistake has occurred in the United States during the twentieth century." Presumably, Bedau and Radelet would have selected the most compelling 23 cases of the innocent executed to prove their proposition. "Yet, in each of these cases, where there is a record to review, there are eyewitnesses, confessions, physical evidence and circumstantial evidence in support of the defendant’s guilt. Bedau has written elsewhere that it is ‘false sentimentality to argue that the death penalty ought to be abolished because of the abstract possibility that an innocent person might be executed when the record fails to disclose that such cases exist.’ . . . (T)he Bedau and Radelet study . . . speaks eloquently about the extraordinary rarity of error in capital punishment." ("Innocents on Death Row?", National Review, September 12, 1994).

Another significant oversight by that study was not differentiating between the risk of executing innocent persons before and after Furman v Georgia (1972). There is, in fact, no proof that an innocent has been executed since 1900. And the probability of such a tragedy occurring has been lowered significantly more since Furman. In the context that hundreds of thousands of innocents have been murdered or seriously injured, since 1900, by criminals improperly released by the U.S. criminal justice system (or not incarcerated at all!), the relevant question is: Is the risk of executing the innocent, however slight, worth the justifications for the death penalty - those being retribution, rehabilitation, incapacitation, required punishment, deterrence, escalating punishments, religious mandates, cost savings, the moral imperative, just punishment and the saving of innocent lives?

Predictably, opponents still continue to fraudulently claim, even today*, that this study has proven that 23 "innocent" people have been executed, even though Bedau and Radelet, the authors of that study, conceded - in 1988 - that neither they nor any previous researchers have proved that any of those executed was innocent: "We agree with our critics that we have not proved these executed defendants to be innocent; we never claimed that we had." (41, 1 Stanford Law Review, 11/1988).
Ann Coulter summarized Cassell and Markham’s findings about the methodology used in Bedau & Radelet in her June 20, 2000 column The last guys 'proved innocent':

Quote:
But the most preposterous and disingenuous aspect of the Bedau-Radelet study was how the study determined which executed men were later "found to be innocent." The authors of the study seemed to have performed no greater examination of guilt than checking in with the defense counsel.

The Bedau-Radelet Study cited such indicia of "innocence" as the executed man's sustained protestations of his innocence (for the record, criminals always claim to be innocent). They relied on confessions by others (murderer etiquette mandates that the first guy executed must confess to all his associates' crimes on his way to the death chamber, no matter how preposterous the claim). They recited opening statements from defense counsel about what the defense intended to prove at trial, even when the defense theory was absurd and no substantiating evidence was ever adduced.

They even relied on works of pure fiction to claim one particular executed man was "innocent."

In arguing the innocence of Joseph Hillstrom, executed for murder in 1930, for example, Bedau and Radelet cite a novel portraying Hillstrom as innocent. They apparently did not attach much weight to the fact that the novel's author explicitly states in the forward that he has written a work of fiction -- "an act of the imagination." Nor were Bedau and Radelet impressed by the author's repeated public statements that he believed the real Joseph Hillstrom to be guilty.

Bedau and Radelet dismiss the confession of another executed man on the grounds that it was "coerced." The confession, they write, was given only "after being held incommunicado for 32 days after his arrest." They neglect to mention that the allegedly innocent man had issued a constant stream of confessions, not only 32 days after being arrested, but also the day after the crime.

By the time they were finished with the Bedau-Radelet Study, Markman and Cassell were able to state without contradiction: There is no documented case of a factually innocent person being executed for at least the past 50 years.
Finally, here are some comments by Paul Cassell himself about the Bedau-Radelet study, from a statement to the House Judiciary Committee in 1993:

Quote:
The authors also have included a great number of cases from the early part of this century, long before the adoption of the extensive contemporary system of safeguards in the death penalty's administration, which greatly skews their analysis... what the authors have done is comparable to studying traffic deaths before the adoption of traffic signals.
He then points out that:

Quote:
Moreover, Bedau and Radelet cite but a single allegedly erroneous execution during the past twenty-five years -- that of James Adams. A dispassionate review of the facts of that case demonstrates, however, that Adams was unquestionably guilty
(He proceeds later to lay out the facts of this case in a way that makes it quite clear that Adams was indeed guilty.)

Cassell continues:

Quote:
Bedau and Radelet's other alleged instances of "innocent" persons executed in earlier parts of this century are equally dubious. In our 1988 article, we reviewed all eleven cases of alleged executions of innocent persons in which appellate opinions set forth facts proved at trial in detail sufficient to permit a neutral observer to assess the validity of Bedau and Radelet's claims, including all of the cases since 1945. That review demonstrated beyond any reasonable doubt that all eleven of those defendants were guilty of capital murder.
Supporting details can be found in the original paper.

Cassell confirms the statements made in the papers cited earlier, and states flatly that based on his analysis of all of the relevant cases cited in Bedau-Radelet:

Quote:
... no innocent person has been executed in this country since at least 1945
Not “There’s no proof that any innocent person has been executed since 1945” but “No innocent person has been executed since 1945.” He’s pretty darn sure of himself on this point, and if you read the relevant section you’ll understand why.

He concludes:

Quote:
The questionable examples in the Bedau-Radelet article make an important point about the debate over mistaken executions. It is easy for opponents of the death penalty to allege, despite a unanimous jury verdict, appellate court review, and denial of executive clemency, that an "innocent" person has been executed. Such an assertion costs nothing and will help abolitionists advance their cause. As this review demonstrates, such claims should be reviewed with a healthy dose of skepticism.

The paucity of examples of innocent defendants who have been executed provides compelling evidence that the risk of mistaken execution is virtually non-existent. If opponents of the death penalty are able to produce no better examples of mistaken executions than those put forward by Bedau and Radelet, then the overwhelming majority of Americans who support capital punishment can rest assured that the criminal justice system is doing an admirable, if not indeed perfect, job of preventing the execution of innocent defendants.
bd-from-kg is offline  
Old 06-20-2003, 08:02 PM   #103
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
Default

Bill Snedden:

Quote:
The fact that we have an intuitive belief that CP should be a stronger deterrent than LIP and yet statistical studies don't seem to bear out this relationship consistently should give us pause, don't you think?
First, it’s not an “intuitive” belief. It’s based on extremely well-established principles of human psychology. The only way that CP could fail to reduce the murder rate would be if something like the “Alonzo effect” exists. But aside from the fact that this seems intuitively implausible, there’s no evidence for any such effect. In the absence of empirical evidence for a hitherto unknown phenomenon, the only rational policy is to assume that it doesn’t exist.

Second, I’ve spent some time explaining why the fact that the older studies fail to show the expected effect should not give us pause. It’s to be expected that such studies would fail to detect the effect given the extreme noisiness of the data. (Look at it. The murder rate in each state jumps up and down from year to year for no discernible reason much more than any plausible estimate of the number of lives that might be saved by the deterrent effect. You wouldn’t expect to detect a “signal” in all this noise unless the signal were very strong indeed, for the same reason that you wouldn’t expect to pick up a distant, weak radio station in the middle of a thunderstorm.

Think about what I pointed out earlier. The Erlich study shows a deterrent effect. But small changes in the model (e.g., in the functional form used to model some of the effects) cause the effect to disappear. Why do you suppose that is? The only possible explanation is that the noise level is simply too high to detect the signal with any reliability. And yet the strength of the effect that Erlich came up with is around eight lives saved per execution. This is a pretty strong effect if it exists. But the data Erlich was working with (which was “state of the art” at the time) was so noisy that even assuming that it exists it was essentially undetectable.

Epidemiological studies have the same problem; they are quite often unable to pick up an effect that shows up clearly in controlled clinical trials. There’s nothing unusual about this. It’s well known that an effect has to be very strong indeed to be detectable in uncontrolled, “real world” data. It’s a fallacy to conclude from the fact that an effect isn’t detected in this kind of study that it probably doesn’t exist.

Quote:
As I see it, this is in fact what we would expect to see if "all things" are indeed not equal.
If all things wsere not equal (by which I assume you mean that there’s an “Alonzo effect”) it would be very surprising if the opposing effects turned out to be equal (or even very close to being equal). After all, a priori we have very little idea of the strength of either effect and no reason at all to expect them to be anywhere close to being equal in magnitude. So given the factors that I mentioned above, the data (i.e., no detectable effect) is explained just as well by the hypothesis that only the deterrent effect exists as by the hypothesis that there are opposing effects that tend to cancel. And the “one-effect” hypothesis is the more parsimonious, so by Ockham’s Razor it wins.

But at this point I have to remind you that it’s no longer true that no effect can be detected. The best studies , namely the more recent ones using more sophisticated methodology and much better (more detailed) data than was available in the past, have been consistently picking up a very substantial deterrent effect.

Quote:
To put it into the terms of your desideratum, as you say, torture may enable a regime to provide the greatest good for the greatest number, but is that the only consideration we would ever want to make? Don't we have a right to be concerned over the means as well as the end?
I suspect that we’re finally getting to the real issue here, at least as far as you and Chris are concerned.

The old adage “the ends don’t justify the means” can be taken to mean two very different things:

(1) The means in question have effects in addition to the ones we’re aiming for (i.e., the “ends”), and these effects are sufficiently negative to outweigh the desirability of the effects that we are aiming for.

(2) The means in question are simply wrong in themselves. No matter how desirable the consequences of using them might be, even after taking absolutely all effects, however distant or indirect, into account, it would still be wrong to use them.

Now the first interpretation is perfectly intelligible, even to a non-theist. But the second one isn’t. The only way (so far as I can see) that a means could be “wrong in itself” regardless of consequences would be if it had an intrinsic property of “ought-not-to-be-doneness”. But (as Alonzo will be happy to elaborate) the concept of an intrinsic property of “ought-not-to-be-doneness” makes no sense in a naturalistic framework.

Thus, if you want to show that a certain measure should not be used, the only way to do it is to show that using it has undesirable consequences that outweigh the desirable consequences (such as deterring the kind of activity for which it is to be used as a punishment). If you can’t show that, you have no case against using it.

That’s why I went to some pains to produce consequence-related reasons why I think that using torture as a punishment would be undesirable. Now it’s your turn. Give me some consequence-related reasons why capital punishment is undesirable.

As I said in my reply to Chris, if you're unable or unwilling to do this, there's little point in continuing the discussion since we have totally incommensurate ideas of what the desideratum is. I flat don't understand deontological moral theories.
bd-from-kg is offline  
Old 06-22-2003, 04:21 AM   #104
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
Default

bd-from-kg
Quote:
That’s why I went to some pains to produce consequence-related reasons why I think that using torture as a punishment would be undesirable.
Yes, but what you didn't do was to explain how you "objectively" came to the conclusion that your undesirable consequences outweighed the benefits of torture.
Quote:
Now it’s your turn. Give me some consequence-related reasons why capital punishment is undesirable.
I think this misses the point. (Unless you're suggesting that there are no undesirable consequences of CP, which I'm sure you're not)

The point at issue here (for me at least) is how we assess the impact of the consequences of a particular punishment on what we wish to achieve and to what degree we can do this objectively.

You said:
Quote:
...the consensus that’s needed is a consensus about what we want the system of justice to do; what the criterion is for comparing one system to another.
But this is the problem - as far as I'm aware there exists no such consensus. At least not to the extent that we can confidently state that any particular form of punishment objectively meets our needs any better than any other. Any judgement will be based either on what we, personally, value or on what we assume others value or ought to value.

Now I'm not suggesting that this lack of clear consensus renders debate and argument meaningless - in fact, just the opposite. The only way we can resolve these issues is by argument and persuasion and, ultimately, by a show of hands.

Because of this lack of consensus, any debate about the pros and cons of any particuar form of punishment is, in reality, a debate about what we want from a "system of justice".

Unless you can demonstrate that there is a sufficient consensus on what "what we want the system of justice to do", then the scope for "objective analysis" in determining the effectiveness of any particular form of punishment is far more limited than you appear to be suggesting.

Chris
The AntiChris is offline  
Old 06-22-2003, 12:17 PM   #105
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
Default

The AntiChris:

Quote:
... what you didn't do was to explain how you "objectively" came to the conclusion that your undesirable consequences outweighed the benefits of torture.
Why, I didn’t come to that conclusion objectively. There’s no such thing as “objective” in this context. Haven’t we been through this before?

If I got a great thrill from knowing that people were being tortured and didn’t care what happened to anyone else, I’d probably conclude that torturing murderers was a great idea. Heck, I’d probably think that torturing innocent young children was a great idea. Could you objectively show me that I was “wrong”?

But fortunately there is a great deal of intersubjective agreement about what sorts of things are desirable and undesirable.

Quote:
The point at issue here (for me at least) is how we assess the impact of the consequences of a particular punishment on what we wish to achieve and to what degree we can do this objectively.
Yes. That’s pretty much what I said in my last reply to you. If we can come to some agreement on how to evaluate the consequences of a CP regime vs. a non-CP one, we can have a productive discussion; otherwise we can’t. Or in other words, we have to have at least a reasonable amount of agreement about what makes one state of affairs more desirable than another before we can talk about whether a CP regime produces a more desirable state of affairs than a non-CP one.

Quote:
bd:
...the consensus that’s needed is a consensus about what we want the system of justice to do; what the criterion is for comparing one system to another.

Chris:
But this is the problem - as far as I'm aware there exists no such consensus.
I don’t agree. I think that there’s a pretty broad consensus that what we’re aiming for as a society is something like the “greatest good of the greatest number”, where “good” is understood to refer to desired mental states (a.k.a. “happiness”) and the avoidance of undesired ones; or as Alonzo would say, the satisfaction of the maximum number of “good” desires. This can be described in other ways: the “general welfare”, “domestic tranquility”, etc. There are some subtle differences between these criteria, but in practice they don’t really amount to much – certainly as they apply to the justice system.

Quote:
Now I'm not suggesting that this lack of clear consensus renders debate and argument meaningless - in fact, just the opposite. The only way we can resolve these issues is by argument and persuasion ...
But what would such “debate and argument” look like? What kind of reasons can you offer for why someone else should desire the same ends that you do? How do you go about “persuading” someone who prefers chocolate milkshakes that he ought to prefer vanilla?

Quote:
... and, ultimately, by a show of hands.
Weren’t you the one who said that “the only way we can resolve this is by consensus?” Voting doesn’t create a consensus (as anyone who remembers the 2000 election must surely understand); it just determines who wins.

Another way to determine who wins is to shoot it out. But in our society, because we have a broad consensus on what we’re aiming for as a society, we have a very strong consensus that deciding what to do by voting is better than doing it with guns (or via any number of other methods, like letting the ayatollahs decide).

Quote:
Because of this lack of consensus, any debate about the pros and cons of any particular form of punishment is, in reality, a debate about what we want from a "system of justice".
Of course I don’t agree about the “lack of consensus”, at least at a fundamental level. I thing that the problem is that a number of people are unwilling to accept that they can’t “have their cake and eat it too”, or in other words, that they can’t have all the things that they desire from the justice system. In particular (as we’ve seen on this thread) a great many people are unwilling to accept the simple fact that capital punishment will deter a number of murders, because accepting it would force them to think seriously about their priorities. What do they desire most: saving thousands of innocent lives, or avoiding the unpleasantness of executing some people? What we see is a policy of deny, deny, deny – of refusing to accept that this is in fact the choice. This has of course been encouraged by a determined, nonstop campaign of misinformation by CP opponents, who are well aware that this is what people want desperately to believe, just as Christianity tells people what they want desperately to believe: that they can receive absolution from their sins and that they can live forever.

Quote:
Unless you can demonstrate that there is a sufficient consensus on what "what we want the system of justice to do", then the scope for "objective analysis" in determining the effectiveness of any particular form of punishment is far more limited than you appear to be suggesting.
Why? The meaning of “effectiveness” with respect to a punishment is not really in dispute: it means “How well (if at all) does it reduce future crimes?” This is a pretty objective question; the only element of subjectivity, so far as I can see, is that people may rate the relative seriousness of various crimes differently. But this doesn’t seem to be a real problem in practice; you don’t see a lot of intense debate over, e.g., whether the justice system is placing too much emphasis on armed robbery relative to embezzlement.

Of course, no one considers the effectiveness of the justice system to be the sole criterion for judging it. If there is a serious disagreement about ends, this is where it is: what else do we want from the system, and how much weight do we give to these other ends relative to the end of suppressing crime? In particular, many people would reply “We want it to produce justice. And this takes priority over all other ends.” This, of course, is a deontological position, and as such is favored mostly by religious people and by some who haven’t thought seriously about moral philosophy. It’s really untenable in the context of nontheism. Naturally consequentialists want “justice” too, but they define “justice” in terms of consequences, and want it because they believe it has desirable consequences, not for its own sake.

This is an example of an important point, and one that often creates a lot of confusion. Most “ends”, on analysis, turn out to be means to further ends, which in turn are often means to still further ends. To think clearly about such things you have to ask yourself whether the ends you have in mind are final or ultimate ends (things that you consider desirable for their own sake) or means to further ends. It often happens that people think that they have an irreconcilable difference about ends when the “ends” then have in mind are actually different means aimed at achieving the same ultimate ends. The disagreement is really, at bottom, a disagreement about how best to achieve these ends. And questions about what means are most efficacious for achieving some agreed-on end are objective.

One other point is worth making. As far as debate or discussion is concerned, it doesn’t matter whether we can achieve society-wide consensus on the criteria for evaluating the results of one policy vs. another. It’s only necessary to have a reasonable amount of consensus among those who are participating. Just as you and I can agree on what movie to go to even if a larger group of people would be unable to.
bd-from-kg is offline  
Old 06-24-2003, 09:39 AM   #106
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
Default

bd-from-kg
Quote:
There’s no such thing as "objective" in this context.
Sure. I was trying to make sense of what you'd said earlier:

"judgment (on where to draw the line) be based on an objective analysis of what measures will best fulfill the function and purpose of the justice system as we see it."

On reflection I realise that I missed the significance of "based on" in this statement.
Quote:
If we can come to some agreement on how to evaluate the consequences of a CP regime vs. a non-CP one, we can have a productive discussion;
But in the absence of this agreement (or at least the absence of an agreement in sufficient detail), any discussion about the relative merits of different forms of punishment is, in part, a debate about how we evaluate consequences.
Quote:
I think that there’s a pretty broad consensus that what we’re aiming for as a society is something like the "greatest good of the greatest number", where "good" is understood to refer to desired mental states (a.k.a. "happiness") and the avoidance of undesired ones;
Yes, of course. But I really don't see how such vague definitions of "greatest good" provide useful guidance for determining which punishment regime yields the "greatest good".
Quote:
But what would such "debate and argument" look like? What kind of reasons can you offer for why someone else should desire the same ends that you do? How do you go about "persuading" someone who prefers chocolate milkshakes that he ought to prefer vanilla?
I'm not sure what point you're making here.

I rather doubt that you're suggesting that any punishment is an "end" in itself.

From the context, I can only think that you're saying that if, as I suggest, there were a "lack of clear consensus", then any debate would be equivalent to arguing the relative merits of milkshake flavours.

I'm afraid you're going to have to explain your thinking. (and bear in mind that at no time have I said that there is a complete absence of any consensus, simply that the consensus that does exist is insufficient and lacks clarity.)
Quote:
Weren’t you the one who said that "the only way we can resolve this is by consensus?" Voting doesn’t create a consensus (as anyone who remembers the 2000 election must surely understand); it just determines who wins.
This seems rather petty. Of course voting doesn't create a consensus - it's simply one method of determining what the consensus might be.
Quote:
In particular (as we’ve seen on this thread) a great many people are unwilling to accept the simple fact that capital punishment will deter a number of murders, because accepting it would force them to think seriously about their priorities.
I have to admit that I've always been a little sceptical of claims that CP has no deterrent power at all or, the even more unconvincing claim, that CP increases murder rates. Anyone who bases their opposition to the CP solely on these dubious claims seems to me to be on rather shaky ground.

Quote:
Chris: Unless you can demonstrate that there is a sufficient consensus on what "what we want the system of justice to do", then the scope for "objective analysis" in determining the effectiveness of any particular form of punishment is far more limited than you appear to be suggesting.

bd: The meaning of "effectiveness" with respect to a punishment is not really in dispute: it means "How well (if at all) does it reduce future crimes?" This is a pretty objective question;
I thought it was pretty clear that I was using the word "effectiveness" in this context with respect to what "we want" with the implicit qualifier - taking account of undesirable consequences. If there is no clear consensus on what constitutes an undesirable consequence or what value we assign it, then the "question" is far from objective.
Quote:
In particular, many people would reply “We want it to produce justice. And this takes priority over all other ends.” This, of course, is a deontological position, and as such is favored mostly by religious people and by some who haven’t thought seriously about moral philosophy. It’s really untenable in the context of nontheism. Naturally consequentialists want “justice” too, but they define “justice” in terms of consequences, and want it because they believe it has desirable consequences, not for its own sake.
I agree completely, though I'm not sure why you felt the need to make this point. This doesn't seem be a problem amongst non-theists around here.
Quote:
And questions about what means are most efficacious for achieving some agreed-on end are objective.
Sure. But the problem with the CP debate is that we don't have agreed-on ends and the data (actual deterrent effect) is less than conclusive.

Earlier, in a response to Bill Snedden, you argued that if there is a serious doubt about the deterrent effect of CP, any reasonable person would execute anyway on the basis that if it turned out that there was no deterrent effect, all we'd have lost is the lives of some brutal murderers.

The clear implication here is that any undesirable consequences of CP are so insignificant that they have a neglgigible effect on the "greatest good". However I'm having trouble reconciling this with your belief that the undesirable consequences of adding torture to the CP would outweigh the undoubted (by your own estimation) benefit gained by the additional innocent lives saved.

What is the reasoning that led you to conclude that the the death of a convicted murderer, with its attendant psychological cruelty, is of negligible significance whereas the torture of a condemned prisoner has such an impact on the "greatest good" that its use cannot be justified?

It seems to me that your evaluation of the two punishments is disproportionate.

Chris
The AntiChris is offline  
Old 06-25-2003, 12:38 PM   #107
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
Default

Quote:
... in the absence of this agreement (or at least the absence of an agreement in sufficient detail), any discussion about the relative merits of different forms of punishment is, in part, a debate about how we evaluate consequences.
But there can’t be a real debate about this. If we truly agree on the consequences of each regime (CP vs. non-CP), any disagreement about their relative merits can only be a disagreement about ultimate ends. And these are not debatable, because no rational reasons can be given for preferring one set of ultimate ends to another, or assigning different priorities to different ultimate ends. That was the point of my comment about the impossibility of debating the relative merits of chocolate vs. strawberry milkshakes. If we agree about consequences, any remaining disagreement is about personal preferences.

Quote:
bd:
I think that there’s a pretty broad consensus that what we’re aiming for as a society is something like the "greatest good of the greatest number", where "good" is understood to refer to desired mental states (a.k.a. "happiness") and the avoidance of undesired ones;

Chris:
Yes, of course. But I really don't see how such vague definitions of "greatest good" provide useful guidance for determining which punishment regime yields the "greatest good".
Although this is of course subjective (how can “what we’re aiming for” be anything but subjective?) I don’t see that it’s particularly vague. There’s a great deal of intersubjective agreement about what mental states are desirable. And in any case we can determine which mental states any given person finds most desirable (and even get a rough ranking of relative desirability of various mental states) by asking him (or perhaps by performing appropriate psychological tests). That would determine what “desirable” means with respect to his mental states, and by doing this for everyone we could (in principle) obtain a complete catalogue of the relative desirability of all mental states.

Anyway, perhaps you’d do better to discuss this with Alonzo, who has discussed this sort of thing extensively.

Quote:
bd:
Voting doesn’t create a consensus (as anyone who remembers the 2000 election must surely understand); it just determines who wins.

Chris:
This seems rather petty. Of course voting doesn't create a consensus - it's simply one method of determining what the consensus might be.
But what you said in your last post was:

Quote:
The only way we can resolve these issues is by argument and persuasion and, ultimately, by a show of hands.
The implication seemed to be that a show of hands would resolve the issue (at least after allowing a sufficiently long time for the issue to be thoroughly debated, so that no further “persuasion” was likely). My point was that a “consensus” is far more than a majority. If, say, 51% of the people favor CP and 49% oppose, the “pro-CP” position will win a “show of hands” even though there’s nothing remotely like a consensus. In fact, even a large majority doesn’t necessarily represent a consensus. For example, if 75% favored CP but 25% were passionately opposed on moral grounds, would that be a “consensus”?

In fact, when there really is a consensus about something a “show of hands” isn’t even necessary, except perhaps to formalize it (e.g., to actually enact it into law).

Quote:
I have to admit that I've always been a little sceptical of claims that CP has no deterrent power at all or, the even more unconvincing claim, that CP increases murder rates. Anyone who bases their opposition to the CP solely on these dubious claims seems to me to be on rather shaky ground.
I’m glad that you recognize this; if only more CP opponents did.

Quote:
I thought it was pretty clear that I was using the word "effectiveness" in this context with respect to what "we want" with the implicit qualifier – taking account of undesirable consequences.
Well, that’s just not how the term “effective” is ordinarily used. For example, if the objective were to stop a fugitive on the Brooklyn Bridge, dropping a 10-megaton nuclear bomb on the bridge would ordinarily be said to be very effective, but the collateral damage might be unacceptably high. Of course, if you propose to use the term in a nonstandard way that’s your privilege, but if you want to communicate with other people you need to warn them about any nonstandard usages.

Quote:
bd:
In particular, many people would reply “We want it to produce justice. And this takes priority over all other ends.” This, of course, is a deontological position, and as such is favored mostly by religious people and by some who haven’t thought seriously about moral philosophy. It’s really untenable in the context of nontheism...

Chris:
I agree completely, though I'm not sure why you felt the need to make this point. This doesn't seem be a problem amongst non-theists around here.
That’s not clear by any means. A good many non-theists here have taken positions on moral questions that can only be considered deontological. Bill Snedden seemed to be taking one on this thread just a while back:

Quote:
Bill Snedden:
Don't you think it's also reasonable that we might want a consensus on how a system of justice does that which we want it to do as well?

... Don't we have a right to be concerned over the means as well as the end?

Don't we really need to answer that question with every form of punishment we establish? Not just what we want as a result, but how we want to get there?
Of course (as I pointed out) it’s possible to interpret this in consequentialist terms, but this interpretation seems pretty strained. This whole post reads exactly like what one might expect from deontologist. And Bill gave no indication that he meant anything other than what his comments seem to mean taken at face value.

Quote:
... the problem with the CP debate is that we don't have agreed-on ends and the data (actual deterrent effect) is less than conclusive.
My whole point is that these are entirely different kinds of problems. the latter one is a disagreement about an empirical question; it can be resolved (in principle) by further study. The former can’t.

Quote:
Earlier, in a response to Bill Snedden, you argued that if there is a serious doubt about the deterrent effect of CP, any reasonable person would execute anyway on the basis that if it turned out that there was no deterrent effect, all we'd have lost is the lives of some brutal murderers. The clear implication here is that any undesirable consequences of CP are so insignificant that they have a negligible effect on the "greatest good".
Jeez, are you guys going to keep beating me over the head with this forever? Give it a rest. All that I meant was that it can be argued that a reasonable person would choose CP over non-CP if he was in doubt about the deterrent effect, since bad guys getting killed isn’t nearly as bad as good guys getting killed. (In fact, really bad guys getting killed is arguably a good thing.) I pointed out at the time that if something like the “Alonzo effect” exists (in other words, if CP has undesirable consequences in addition to any deterrent effect) this could invalidate the argument. But it’s true that I find this possiblity quite remote. I’ve stated my reasons for this opinion at some length.

Quote:
What is the reasoning that led you to conclude that the the death of a convicted murderer, with its attendant psychological cruelty, is of negligible significance whereas the torture of a condemned prisoner has such an impact on the "greatest good" that its use cannot be justified?
I’ve already stated my reasoning. (See my June 18 post.) But here’s another argument along the same lines:

We (as a society) have no choice but to kill people under some circumstances regardless of whether we have CP. For example, police must be allowed to shoot a dangerous criminal if he tries to escape (or to evade capture in the first place), and lesser force won’t stop him. We also have no choice but to engage in defensive wars from time to time, and in any war a number of people are going to be killed – some of them innocents. As we’ve learned to our sorrow, when dealing with terrorists we have no real choice but to go on the offensive to disrupt the terrorist organizations before they strike, and this may involve an offensive war against another country (as in Afghanistan).

On the other hand, there are few if any occasions where we have no real choice but to torture someone. If torture came to be used as a punishment, it would be something “new and strange”. There are no occasions where torture is now considered acceptable, and no occasions where the government is authorized to use it. Thus it would break a very strong, almost universally accepted taboo. And for this reason it could prove to be brutalizing in ways that CP is not. (In fact, I think the “could” here is too weak; it almost certainly would be brutalizing in ways that CP isn't.)

Now when are you going to offer some counterarguments so that we have something to discuss? Maybe you can start by explaining why you think that CP involves “attendant psychological cruelty”. Is this just another way of saying that the condemned man fears being executed? If so, doesn’t the same apply to any punishment? After all, the point of sanctions is that they’re feared; that’s why they deter.
bd-from-kg is offline  
Old 06-25-2003, 03:03 PM   #108
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: Greensboro, NC, U.S.A.
Posts: 2,597
Talking Well, I never!

Rules? We don' need no stinkin' rules!!

Alright, bd, I ain't no stinkin' deontologist!

I simply can't have that kind of epithet hanging out there. What will people think?

For the record: I am a consequentialist, albeit not a utilitarian. I consider my moral schema closer to ethical egoism, but a rather odd, societal version of it.

I'm going to respond in more detail later today or early tomorrow, but I wanted to get that straight right away!

I also want to thank you for getting me to think harder about this topic than I have in the past 10 years. When I was a Christian, I came to oppose CP on religious grounds and sort of carried that opposition through my "deconversion" by grounding it in my beliefs regarding proper use of political force and individual liberties. At any rate, I'll allow that you've poked some holes in some of my cherished ideals and I'm struggling a bit for ways to patch them up...

Regards,

Bill Snedden
Bill Snedden is offline  
Old 06-25-2003, 08:26 PM   #109
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
Default Re: Well, I never!

Bill Snedden:

Quote:
Alright, bd, I ain't no stinkin' deontologist! :D

I simply can't have that kind of epithet hanging out there. What will people think? ;)
Well! Glad to hear it! As I've said before, I can make no sense of deontological moral systems.

As you probably noticed, I was careful not to state flat-out that you are a deontologist, only that this was the most natural, straightforward interpretation of some of your comments.

Quote:
I also want to thank you for getting me to think harder about this topic than I have in the past 10 years.
Even more glad to hear that. That's the purpose of these forums, isn't it?

Actually my support of CP is no more "written in stone" than Alonzo's opposition to it. It's an uncomfortable position. (But I'd be even more uncomfortable trying to explain to a grieving mother of a little girl who was kidnapped, tortured, and murdered why I was complicit in preventing the government from doing everything in its power [within reason] to prevent this tragedy, and why the guy who did it is going to get three squares a day and free lodging for the rest of his life instead of getting back at least a little of what he gave to her child.) My primary concern has been to debunk what I consider to be clearly unsound (or hopelessly inadequate) arguments against CP. If somone comes up with a good argument against it (and your and Chris's recent posts seem to me to be the only promising direction in which to look for such arguments) I'll be more than happy to consider them seriously. But naturally I'll keep up my end as well as I can. After all, how can you tell whether an argument is good if no one is willing to test it?
bd-from-kg is offline  
Old 06-26-2003, 10:06 AM   #110
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
Default

bd-from-kg
Quote:
Now when are you going to offer some counterarguments so that we have something to discuss?


Like Bill, our discussion has given me some serious food for thought and my thinking on CP is currently in a state of flux.

Quote:
Maybe you can start by explaining why you think that CP involves "attendant psychological cruelty". Is this just another way of saying that the condemned man fears being executed? If so, doesn’t the same apply to any punishment?
I don't think so. Just as you argue that torture is cruel and unusual, I'd say the mental anguish endured by a condemned prisoner is unique and of a completely different order to that experienced by a prisoner serving a life sentence. I suppose the closest equivalent is the mental anguish endured by someone diagnosed with a terminal illness who has a very short time to live.

I think it's the deliberate infliction of this aspect of CP that sets it apart, in a very distinct way, from those situations where we accept the killing of someone in self-defence or when they pose an imminent threat to others.

I've avoided the use of the word "brutalising" so far because I'm not at all sure what we mean by it. When you say torture could "prove to be brutalising", do you mean that society could simply become inured or desensitised resulting in a less compassionate society? Or do you think brutalisation could directly result in an increase in undesirable behaviour?
Quote:
If torture came to be used as a punishment, it would be something “new and strange”. There are no occasions where torture is now considered acceptable, and no occasions where the government is authorized to use it. Thus it would break a very strong, almost universally accepted taboo. And for this reason it could prove to be brutalizing in ways that CP is not. (In fact, I think the “could” here is too weak; it almost certainly would be brutalizing in ways that CP isn't.)
It's clear that you believe the process of brutalisation occurs when a practice, previously considered unacceptable, is introduced by some authority such as the government. Is there any reason why this process wouldn't work in reverse? If brutalisation is something to be avoided, then wouldn't the abolition of CP and the universal condemnation of all killing other than for reasons of self-defense, protection of others in imminent danger and mercy killing, have a 'debrutalising' (civilising) effect?

In fact, isn't this one of the processes that's lead to our current state of "civilisation"?

Chris
The AntiChris is offline  
 

Thread Tools Search this Thread
Search this Thread:

Advanced Search

Forum Jump


All times are GMT -8. The time now is 05:33 AM.

Top

This custom BB emulates vBulletin® Version 3.8.2
Copyright ©2000 - 2015, Jelsoft Enterprises Ltd.