Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
06-14-2003, 03:43 PM | #91 | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Bill Snedden:
Sorry that this is so long, but we seem to disagree on so many points that it seems unavoidable. Since it’s so long I omitted some quotes from the previous post(s) that might have made it easier to follow. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
The “desire-belief-action” model actually applies even to the more intelligent animals in most cases. If a cat desires food [what cat doesn’t!] and believes that there’s a reasonable probability that it will find food at a certain place, this will motivate it to go there. But if it also believes that there’s a chance that a dangerous dog will be there, that will motivate it not to go there. The decision will depend on the relative strength of the two desires and the subjective probability of finding food and finding the dog. (It will also depend, of course, on what else it wants and what alternatives are available.) None of this depends in the least on the assumption that the cat understands what a “probability” is, or on the assumption that it will stop to reflect on the situation, and certainly not on the assumption that its decision will be “rational” in some sense. A model that applies even to hungry cats will certainly apply to would-be murderers, unless they’re completely bonkers, like the guy who took his wife for a hat rack. Quote:
But it’s true that there seems to be a disconnect between the professed beliefs of many religious people and their attitudes and actions. Bertrand Russell commented that he once asked a good Christian lady whose husband had died where she thought he was now. Her answer was along the lines of “Oh, no doubt he’s in Heaven enjoying eternal bliss. But do we have to discuss such unpleasant subjects?” The actual behavior of many religious people suggests that they don’t really believe what they profess to believe. Or else they’ve managed to completely compartmentalize their religious beliefs from “real life” so that the one has no effect on the other. Of course, this doesn’t apply to all religious people; some are clearly sincere and take their beliefs seriously. But those are the very people who do worry seriously about their sins and getting to Heaven. Quote:
Many people do seem to have a subconscious belief along the lines of “nothing bad will happen to me if I exercise reasonable care and prudence.” Or in other words, that in the final analysis their fate is in their own hands. (An illusion, of course.) But the death penalty can be expected to convince many such people that murder is quite imprudent, that by killing someone they may be bringing the awful fate of being executed on themselves. Quote:
That’s not to say that a theory like Alonzo’s is irrational. (I find it implausible, but that’s another thing entirely.) Unlike you (and some others) he argues that there’s another (subtle, long-term) effect of CP that offsets the deterrent effect. This is not at all the same as claiming that the deterrent effect doesn’t exist in the first place. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
The correct question is whether the threat of execution deters some people from doing such things, not whether it prevents everyone from doing it. There’s another important point here as well. Suppose that we know that a given sanction will prevent some people from doing X, but not only will it not prevent some others from doing X, it will fail to prevent anyone from doing Y, which pretty much everyone regards as being even worse than X. Shall we then refuse to exercise the sanction against those who do Y on the grounds that it doesn’t deter anyone from doing it? Certainly not. The justice system must be seen as doing justice, or at least approximating it to the best of our ability. If people are to be punished for doing X, they must be punished at least as severely for doing Y. Otherwise the entire system would be (quite properly) seen as not even being aimed at justice, which would be disastrous. Similarly, suppose that we know that there is a certain class of criminal so incorrigible that they will kidnap young girls, etc. (or whatever) no matter what the legal sanction is. Should we then refuse to punish criminals of this class? Certainly not. To punish those who commit identical offenses because they are less incorrigible while refusing to punish those who are the most incorrigible would regarded as an intolerable travesty of justice by any civilized society. Finally, justice requires that, so far as possible, significantly worse crimes receive significantly worse punishment, and that more crimes of the same kind be punished more severely than less. Of course, at some point we’ll reach the worst punishment that we’re prepared to inflict on anyone. But the lower we set this “maximum sanction”, the lower we’ll be forced to set the sanctions for lesser offenses in order to satisfy this basic principle of justice. For example, if we are not prepared to execute anyone, ever, then a murderer already serving a life sentence has no reason not to kill again, for whatever reason strikes his fancy. Thus, the question of whether a given sanction did, or might have, deterred a given person from a given crime is not the only relevant question. We must also consider whether the system as a whole is seen as being just, or at any rate as just as humanly possible. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
But this case brings up another point that’s often overlooked. It may be that by the time he was caught Dahmer couldn’t help himself. But there had to be an earlier point in his life when he could have helped himself; when his depravity was not so far advanced or had not even begun to develop yet. And at that point a sufficiently strong sanction (such as a strong probability of swift execution) would almost certainly have been able to deter him. At any rate, the fact that he had a choice at some point in his life – to take the path he did or choose another - makes him completely culpable regardless of whether he was beyond restraining himself later on. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
This whole argument depends on an equivocation about what it means to “deliberately kill an innocent person”. You’re treating “(deliberately kill) an innocent person” as meaning the same thing as “deliberately (kill an innocent person)”. Here’s an example to illustrate the point. I’m a policeman. I see someone shooting several innocent people, and I see someone who looks like the shooter fleeing the scene with a gun. I go after him, identify myself, and order him to stop. He turns and points what appears to be a gun at me. I shoot to kill, and I do kill. But it turns out that it wasn’t the shooter. (Maybe he didn’t even have a gun.) I killed an innocent person, and I intended to kill him. But I did not intend to kill an innocent person. This is a particularly good example because it’s very similar to a number of real-life incidents. And it’s closely analogous to mistakenly executing an innocent person. And it’s clear that there is no moral culpability involved. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
To put it another way, deontological moral theories just don’t seem to make sense in the absence of some “divinely revealed” moral principles. Once you decide to ignore consequences in judging the morality of acts, there’s nothing left but arbitrary preference. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
The point is that what’s wrong for an individual is not necessarily wrong for the state. The state is in a very different moral position from the individual by virtue of having taken on the responsibility for enforcing the social contract while forbidding us to do so. |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
06-15-2003, 11:25 AM | #92 | ||||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
NHGH:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Look. Let’s imagine that prosecutors did have the power to offer execution as an option. Can you seriously imagine suspects accepting execution to save themselves from the even more horrible fate of going to prison? Who do you think you’re kidding here? Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Also, a fundamental psychological principle is that of a learned response. When a subject is given a positive experience after doing something, this serves as an incentive to do the same thing again, and conversely when he’s subjected to a negative experience it serves as a “negative incentive” (i.e., a deterrent) to his doing it again – i.e., he becomes more averse to doing it. This is over and above any effect created by abstract knowledge that the experience will be a consequence of the action. (Example: repeated exposure to severe electrical shocks will produce a stronger aversion to electrical shocks than mere abstract knowledge that they’re painful.) In other words, actual experience of a negative incentive increases the aversion to it rather than decreasing it as you suggest. Now I want to go back to a statistic that you keep harping on: Quote:
Here is the actual relevant figure (according to Dudley Sharp of Justice for All, a pro-death-penalty group): Quote:
And it’s far from clear that a significant number of those who waived appeals did so because they would prefer execution to life in prison. Death row isn’t a bit like ordinary prison. It’s very grim, and everyone there knows that there’s a good chance that he’ll be executed. Most of these “volunteers” may have known that there was virtually no chance of their appeals succeeding, and given that they had nothing to look forward to but more time on death row followed by execution, just decided to get it over with. But there’s another factor that you haven’t mentioned: the number of “volunteers” has risen sharply in recent years (padding the statistics), and death penalty opponents attribute this to increasingly inhuman conditions on death row. See for example, this article from Reuters and this one by Roger Hummel. In any case, it stands to reason that the number of people who have a basic preference for death over life in prison has not suddenly changed dramatically, so the rise in “volunteer executions” must be a result of some change in circumstances. All in all, it’s clear that the number of people who prefer execution to life in prison is vanishingly small – a tiny fraction of 1%; probably less than 0.1%. So we must conclude that almost everyone fears execution more than life in prison – which is to say that the threat of execution is more of a deterrent for almost everyone than the threat of life without parole. Frankly, both your post and much of Bill Snedden’s strike me as elaborate attempts to deny the obvious. Are you seriously denying that almost everyone is more averse to being fried than being jailed? If not, what’s your point? Merely that this hasn’t been scientifically proven to your satisfaction? Any serious discussion of capital punishment has to start from the premise that it’s more of a deterrent than life imprisonment. It would be nice if we could have the best of both worlds –a system in which no one is ever executed and which prevents as many murders as possible. But we can’t. We have to decide whether eliminating the death penalty is worth the lives of a significant number of innocent people. |
||||||||||
06-15-2003, 12:01 PM | #93 | ||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Alonzo Fyfe:
I’ll now examine your proposed mechanisms for an “enhancement” effect that might conceivably offset the deterrence effect. This is of some importance because when one is making an extraordinary claim it is almost mandatory to support it by proposing a plausible mechanism – an unusual causal relationship or state of affairs that applies to the specific case at hand and not to the myriad of “normal” cases where the standard rule applies – that could account for it. Thus, one of the main reasons why ESP claims are generally rejected by well-informed rational people is that there is no plausible mechanism: nothing that is known about the real world could account for how information might pass from one mind to another other than through the known mechanisms of sensory perception. In the absence of any such mechanism the presumption is so strong against the existence of such a phenomenon that one is justified in assuming that any statistical evidence presented for ESP is either faked or a product of selection bias (results unfavorable to the hypothesis are ignored and only favorable ones are presented.) Only very strong, incontrovertible evidence to the contrary would justify abandoning this presumption. Now let’s look at your theories about how the DP could have an effect that could increase the murder rate. Quote:
Later you suggest that a reduction in capital punishment might Quote:
A very important exception to the “killing is wrong” rule, of course, is war. All societies either are prepared to fight wars themselves or depend on “patron states” that will fight in their behalf if necessary. And it’s not always feasible to wait until one is attacked. Israel’s Six day War is a perfect illustration; if they’d waited until the attack came they’d have been annihilated. And in this day of international terrorism it’s sometimes necessary (or at least morally defensible) to destroy the terrorists who are working to destroy you before their plots reach fruition. Now in a war even the enemy combatants are often innocent; either they’re being forced to fight or have been misled. No nation can refuse to fire at such soldiers on moral grounds unless it is willing to commit suicide on behalf of its moral principles. And, of course, even in this time of high-tech weaponry it’s inevitable that some completely innocent civilians will be killed; in fact, in some cases the soldiers will know in advance that some specific civilians will be killed (for example, if they blow up a bridge). Only a complete imbecile is unable to make the kinds of elementary moral distinctions involved in these examples - and for that very reason imbeciles are not considered moral agents. So your concern that some people will conclude that there’s nothing wrong with killing in general merely because they learn that society makes exceptions to this rule in some cases is completely misplaced for anyone who can remotely be considered a moral agent. Later you give it another try: Quote:
So it’s not at all clear why a child (even a very precocious child, who had some real grasp of the issues involves) would conclude from the fact that his society does not use the DP that it is more committed to the principle that killing is (almost) never okay than a society that uses it. In fact, if he did conclude this he would be mistaken. It’s more likely that such a society is simply more cost-conscious, or more pessimistic about its effectiveness, or more averse to killing innocents (but with no objection to killing the guilty) or more averse to discriminatory outcomes. Besides, the idea that a six-to-eight-year-old’s basic moral attitudes are going to be significantly affected merely by the abstract knowledge that his society uses the DP is ludicrous. Children at this age are not terribly cerebral. They’re much more affected by their own experiences, the example set by their parents, and to a lesser extent by what they actually see with their own eyes (even if only on television or in a movie). Any abstract knowledge that they might happen to acquire about their country’s legal system is going to be so far down the scale influence-wise as to be virtually nonexistent. Only a person who has had no actual experience with children of this age could possibly believe that their moral attitudes are affected by knowledge of whether their country uses capital punishment. And the vast majority of them will have no idea whether it does or not anyway; six-to-eight-year-olds are not exactly avid newspaper readers or fans of the six o’clock news. The violence the children see on television and in the movies is far more likely to affect their attitudes than the kind of abstract knowledge that you’re talking about. This is especially true because children at that age don’t distinguish as clearly as adults between reality and make-believe. They know (generally) that what they see on TV, etc. is fiction, but its effect on their attitudes (their tastes and aversions) is closer to what the effect would be of seeing the same kind of thing in “real life” than it would be for adults. And this sort of thing very likely has a significant effect even on adults. Finally, you offer this version: Quote:
In fact, this argument is so manifestly absurd if we start from the premise that executing people is sometimes morally justified (or even morally mandated) that one must conclude that it must really be based on the opposite premise: that capital punishment is always morally wrong; that no one ever deserves to be killed. But of course if no one ever deserves to be killed, capital punishment is wrong and should be abolished; end of discussion. So this entire argument is nothing more than an elaborate form of question-begging. Yet another version of this sort of thing often encountered in the literature is that capital punishment is “brutalizing”, meaning apparently that it produces more “brutal” attitudes or sensibilities in those who are aware of it. Once again the implausibility of this idea is obvious. People are not “brutalized” by abstract knowledge, but be actual experiences. And ordinarily the experiences in question have to brutal to be brutalizing. So in the final analysis this is just a fancy way of expressing the opinion the capital punishment is “brutal” – i.e., the sort of thing the brutes – i.e., beings who are not fully human – would do. To anyone who regards capital punishment (as practiced in the U.S. at least) as a just, measured penalty for criminals who display a wanton disregard for human life, this argument is absurd on its face. If anything, the sight of a man who has committed an especially brutal series of murders walking out of the courtroom to a life of three squares a day courtesy of the state is far more likely to be brutalizing than the knowledge that he will pay the just penalty for his acts. Thus the mechanisms that you propose are hopelessly implausible on their face. If there were some convincing actual evidence that they exist, this wouldn’t matter so much; sufficiently good evidence can overcome even a strong prime facie presumption against a theory. But unfortunately, so far as I know there is no such evidence. If there is, by all means bring it to our attention. But if not, these theories can be dismissed out of hand. |
||||
06-15-2003, 01:46 PM | #94 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
|
Quote:
By your reasoning, it would seem that a penalty more fearsome than the current method of execution (such as torture and humiliation prior to a prolonged and painful death) would be an even greater deterrent. Would you endorse such measures? If not, why not? How do you draw the line between between what is effective but unacceptable and what may be slightly less effective but acceptable? Chris |
|
06-18-2003, 07:47 AM | #95 | |||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
The AntiChris:
Quote:
Quote:
A further comment on this may be in order. For consequentialists the justice of a penalty depends on its overall effects (not necessarily just its deterrent or suppression effects, but nevertheless on its effects and nothing else). So it could be argued that CP is unjust precisely because of its brutalizing effects. But if the supposed brutalizing effects depend on its being unjust, this argument is transparently circular. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
The most obvious answer is that such punishments would be unjust. But the problem with that answer is that different people have different notions of “justice”; what seems unjust to me may seem perfectly just to thee and vice versa. There doesn’t seem to be any objective standard of “justice”, or what constitutes a “just” punishment. But this suggests a more reasonable answer: (1) Such punishments would be generally regarded as unjust. As I pointed out in my last reply to Bill Snedden, the “justice system” must be seen as dispensing justice, or at least doing its best to do so. I think that a society in which the laws are generally seen as fundamentally unjust must inevitably collapse. Does this mean that such measures would be acceptable if they were generally regarded as just? So far as this answer is concerned, the answer is “yes”. And it’s not at all clear that there’s a better one. After all, the Romans routinely used crucifixion, which is a form of prolonged torture and humiliation. (Being “hung from a tree was regarded as the ultimate humiliation in those times.) Is there an objective standard by which crucifixion can be called “unjust” (or simply “wrong” for that matter)? More recently, it was common in England (and I believe in some other countries) to execute someone who had committed a serious offence against the Crown by beheading him and displaying his head on a pole for some time – the point being largely to humiliate the person and his family. Was this wrong? It certainly strikes us, with our modern sensibilities, as pointlessly cruel, but apparently it didn’t strike the people living at the time as being so. So it may be that the question of what punishments are appropriate or just in a given society is simply a matter of what “works” for the society in question. Another possible answer is: (2) Such punishments violate the “social contract”. I don’t subscribe to “social contract” theory as a moral philosophy, but it has a lot going for it as a fruitful way of thinking about moral issues, especially the kind that involve society as a whole. Now it’s arguable that people are willing to accept a small risk of being mistakenly executed in return for a substantial reduction in the risk of being murdered, but that they are not willing to accept even a small risk of being tortured and humiliated, etc., even in return for a greater reduction in the risk of being murdered. And the chances of being tortured, etc. by a criminal are vanishingly small. Also, it’s not unreasonable to imagine that there’s a small chance that one might actually murder someone and would be willing to “pay the price” of being executed, but would not be willing to be tortured, etc. Thus it can be reasonably argued that most people in our society would not be willing to enter into a “social contract” that involved the possibility of being subjected to punishments more severe than execution, but would be willing to accept the possibility of execution because it’s not significantly worse than some of the crimes that they face a nontrivial risk of experiencing. Yet another answer that suggests itself is: (3) Punishments that involve torture, humiliation, and the like really are brutalizing. Here again the difference between such punishments and execution is that such things (unlike killing) are quite rare in our society as things stand, so that introducing them as punishments would increase their frequency enormously. Moreover, execution (if it’s performed in a reasonably humane manner) merely subjects the convicted person to something that he will inevitably experience anyway someday. But the same cannot be said of torture and humiliation. Such measures smack of vengeance, not justice, and the appetite for vengeance is something that we must not feed, but rather must be vigilant to suppress, if we are to remain a civilized society. But none of these arguments is a slam dunk, and moreover it can be argued that similar arguments can be mounted against capital punishment. Where should we draw the line, and why? Or shouldn’t there be a line? For example, is torture perhaps an acceptable punishment for criminals who torture their victims? Any other thoughts on this? |
|||||
06-18-2003, 09:14 AM | #96 |
Senior Member
Join Date: Sep 2001
Location: Prague, Czech Republic
Posts: 965
|
Death penalty says: "This person can never be corrected and must be put to death." On the other hand, life imprisonment with a possibility of conditional release after twenty years says: "We believe that this person can never be corrected. But we might be wrong."
Nope, it doesn’t say that. It says, "All things considered, sentencing this person to life with possible parole/death penalty appears to be the best course of action." And what other reasons do you assume? To deny a chance of release to a criminal who can be reformed is to deny justice; to release a criminal who hasn't been reformed is to endanger the society. Don’t presume to say what other people’s reasons are for doing what they do, or for favoring this policy or that. It’s just barely possible that someone might favor the death penalty in one cases, life with parole in another, and life without parole in a third simply because he feels that these are the just, appropriate punishments in each case. Now I don't understand where you are going with this statement. Most of the objections [in the Amnesty International Report] are not to capital punishment per se but to inappropriate applications of it. I didn’t say “all”, I said “most”. And I granted that. Amnesty International also addresses this issue [of possible execution of innocents]: [Their] answer is nonsensical. If death penalty opponents don’t have time to make their case, what do they have time for? Seriously, do you suggest that they ought to spend time and money to overturn convictions of people who have already been put to death? Aren't they better spent on someone who can be helped? In fact, this is what they do; the case of Anthony Porter (Illinois, 1998) whose innocence was proven 48 hours before his scheduled execution by a group of students is an example. And they do have time to make their case. They point out cases when the executed person may have been innocent. But at the moment, trying to prove their innocence at a court is a waste of resources. Are they busy trying to break into the prisons where the executions are taking place and trying to stop them? Give me a break. Do I have to comment on this baseless accusation? It’s beyond understanding why AI thinks that new cases of this kind will miraculously come to light as a result of abolishing the DP. Just like they "miraculously" came into light after death penalty was abolished in United Kingdom. Yes, right. There is an estimate that about twenty innocent people were executed during the past 100 years. Wow. I’m impressed. I estimate that perhaps one innocent person was executed during that time. Sorry, I don’t have a source either. After a short search on Internet, I found out where this number is from. It is a study by Hugo Bedau and Michael Radelet, named "Miscarriages of Justice in Potentially Capital Cases". Mike Rosoft |
06-19-2003, 09:15 AM | #97 | ||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
|
bd-from-kg
Quote:
As a society, the only way we can resolve this is by consensus. As individuals, I think the only thing we can ask is that any judgement on where the line is to be drawn should, as far as possible, not be based on ignorance or false information. Quote:
Of course, as reasonable people, we try to justify our personal distaste, or preference, for certain forms of punishment by appealing to "facts" or "evidence". However, at root, our attitudes to CP are formed from a combination of perceived "facts" about the real world effects of the death penalty and our individual values and emotional preferences. I personally find the notion of taking a captive prisoner who is no longer a danger to society and cold bloodedly executing him, repugnant. Of course it can be argued that his execution may save innocent lives by deterring potential murderers. However, as you yourself have demonstrated, the ability of a punishment to deter is not the sole criterion we use to determine its acceptability - we each draw our own line, based on our own values and principles. I think it's indisputable that most "western" and "enlightened" societies have abolished CP. Although this doesn't help us decide where the line should be drawn, I think it does give an indication as to where the line is drawn in most civilized societies. Chris |
||
06-19-2003, 09:20 AM | #98 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: UK
Posts: 5,932
|
Duplicate post - "server busy" cockup.
|
06-19-2003, 01:38 PM | #99 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jun 2000
Location: Greensboro, NC, U.S.A.
Posts: 2,597
|
Alas! Maligned and misunderstood...
bd-from-kg:
I was originally going to respond point-by-point, but upon reflection, I don't think it would be of any value. So far I've apparently been unable to communicate exaclty what I mean. I think I can sum it all up with one of the last points to which you responded: Quote:
In other words, just as I said, I question whether or not "all things" are or really can be seen as equal in the circumstances we see in capital crimes. The fact that we have an intuitive belief that CP should be a stronger deterrent than LIP and yet statistical studies don't seem to bear out this relationship consistently should give us pause, don't you think? As I see it, this is in fact what we would expect to see if "all things" are indeed not equal. I'll leave out the rest of the stuff as it really bears on why we should be so concerned given that the data doesn't bear out the relationship we intuitively believe to be true rather than the argument itself. Still, I think the AntiChris has made a rather interesting point regarding the legitimacy of particular forms of punishment... Regards, Bill Snedden |
|
06-20-2003, 12:22 PM | #100 | ||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
The AntiChris:
Quote:
Now if your desideratum when it comes to justice is simply to make yourself “feel good”, then the fact that you experience a certain emotion when you contemplate certain forms of punishment is dispository: implementing such a punishment doesn’t make you feel good, and that’s that. But if your desideratum is (like mine) to put into place the regime that is most likely to produce the greatest good of the greatest number (or as Alonzo would say, to satisfy the most “good” desires) we have a basis for a fruitful discussion. Otherwise we’ll be wasting our time: I’ll be arguing that such-and-such a measure is likely to conduce to the greatest good, while you’ll be replying that this may be true, but it doesn’t make you feel good. Quote:
Isn’t that exactly what CP opponents are arguing in effect? Polls show that CP is favored by a substantial majority, but CP opponents say that it should be abolished anyway. Aren’t they saying that the majority is wrong in some sense? And if not in the sense that I just described, what sense are they talking about? Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
A couple of examples should make this clear. Suppose that you believe in equal rights, tolerance, etc., but the sight of a couple of mixed race just makes you sick. Should you base your decision as to whether to support a ban on interracial marriage on your considered views on civil rights, etc., or on your emotional reaction? Or again, say that you firmly believe that people should be allowed to do what they want so long as they don’t hurt anyone else, but you find the idea of homosexuality totally repugnant. Should you base your views on laws banning homosexual acts on your beliefs about personal freedom or on your distaste for homosexual acts? Quote:
Quote:
You also mention “values and principles”. These are legitimate considerations, but typically one has a great many values, and they sometimes conflict with one another. For example, I hold it as an important value that a person should not be punished for a crime that he did not commit. Another major value for me is liberty: people should be free to go about their business; they should not be coerced to do things they don’t want to or to stay in a place they want to leave. I also hold it as an important value that people (especially innocent, law-abiding ones) should be protected from social predators: thieves, con artists, rapists, murderers, etc. Unfortunately these values conflict in a number of respects: prisons severely restrict the freedom of those who are placed in them, punishing anyone for anything always runs the risk of punishing an innocent person, etc. So in basing your position on “your values and principles” it’s important to consider whether your “emotional preferences” are causing you to focus excessively on some of your values while losing sight of others that may be equally important to you. Quote:
In any case, as I pointed out earlier, the great majority of western countries that have abolished CP have done so against the wishes of their own citizens. So all that the fact that CP has been abolished in these countries tells us is that a small, undemocratic political elite opposes CP there. Considering the other policies that this elite favors, that doesn’t impress me in the least. |
||||||||
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|