Freethought & Rationalism ArchiveThe archives are read only. |
02-01-2003, 02:01 PM | #131 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jan 2002
Location: Sweden
Posts: 2,567
|
Quote:
So, you have no objections regarding my views on the so-called standard usages of "objective"? I can't see any. So, the "standard" usage of those words are inadequate, wouldn't you agree? All I see is you waving of my words saying that you are not interested. I guess I will have to find other kids to play. And as for memory as evidence, your reply looks more like a christian saying "There is evidence for god, you cannot see it, and I don't want to show it to you, but it is there. I know it.". The only conclution I can draw from this is that the circle you were talking about exists only in a misinterpreted version of my argument. The one that says that the memory checks it's own consistency. |
|
02-01-2003, 02:20 PM | #132 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Mar 2002
Location: Planet Lovetron
Posts: 3,919
|
Kenny and bd-from-kg, I really applaud the level of this debate. The quality of this exchange has been outstanding.
Quick question Kenny: I'm reading through The Will to Believe , by William James. I've noticed a lot of similarity to his ideas about justification and yours (and, I suppose by extension, Plantinga's). Would you consider Plantinga's notion of warrant to be in anyway dependant on James? |
02-01-2003, 07:34 PM | #133 | ||
Senior Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: South Bend IN
Posts: 564
|
Quote:
Quote:
Now, in my response to bd (which struck me as a more pragmatic type view of rational justification, though bd holds a correspondence view of truth and not a pragmatist view), I did use arguments very similar to those of James to show that, even on bd’s view, belief in God might be construed as practically basic. But, as I argue later on, I think bd’s notion of rational justification is deficient. God Bless, Kenny P.S. (added after first posting) Though, on the other hand, there do seem to be echoes of James’ views in Plantinga, though Plantinga radically parts with James, with respect to Plantinga’s notion of “proper functioning” in a particular environment, so perhaps there are influences. I’m not sure. |
||
02-02-2003, 11:27 AM | #134 | |||||||||
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: King George, VA
Posts: 1,400
|
Kenny:
It often happens that fallacious arguments are much easier to state than to refute. Your last post is a great example. So forgive me if my reply is considerably longer than the original post. (Someone else might do better; I’m not good at being concise anyway.) Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
It might be argued that these numerous ontological premises could be replaced with one all-purpose one that might read something like, “God created the universe to be as it is for reasons known only to Himself”. But if this sort of thing were permissible the MN axioms could be pared down in the same way to read, “The universe is as it is for unknown reasons”. However, this sort of thing is not permissible. The whole point of an ontology is to allow us to interpret and predict; it has to be detailed enough to provide understanding and make predictions at a detailed level. Indeed, a major objection to the “God hypothesis” is that it really doesn’t help us to interpret or predict any experiences at all. Any number of events, and of aspects of the universe, seem to be inconsistent with the God hypothesis, and when confronted with them theists invariably answer with some variant of “we don’t know how God would act; we can’t say anything meaningful about how God might be expected to do things; God works in mysterious ways.” (Kuyper has exemplified this nicely in this very thread.) Since the whole purpose of an ontology is to conceptualize, interpret and predict our actual experiences, there is absolutely no justification for including superfluous premises that don’t contribute anything at all to our ability to do so. Quote:
In all of these cases the explanations involve “high-level” descriptions of natural phenomena. All of the events involved can be, and in fact are being, explained in terms of fundamental natural laws. But complex phenomena are often best understood or in terms of a hierarchy of levels of interpretation. A good illustration of the principle is a computer executing a good chess-playing program. On one level, everything can be explained (in principle) in terms of the movements of the individual molecules and electrons that compose the computer. At the next level we can explain it in terms of the operations of the hard drive, the RAM, the innumerable components of the CPU, etc. The next level of explanation talks about the instructions in the program and how the computer’s operations are “executing” them. Finally we reach a level where we’re talking about chess strategy and tactics, and explain that the computer sacrificed its bishop in order to be able to enforce the advance of a pawn to the eighth rank, where it will queen, giving it a clear winning advantage. The important thing to notice here is that these high-level explanations do not supersede or contradict the lowest-level explanation, but are actually part of it. They involve calling attention to certain patterns in the motions of the molecules and electrons composing the computer which are far from apparent at first sight. The high-level explanations are elaborations of the lowest-level explanation, not de novo explanations of an entirely different kind. The exact same thing is true of meteorological, thermodynamical, biological, and personal explanations. No one imagines that the weather follows “laws” of its own that have nothing to do with the basic natural laws that underlie all natural phenomena. Similarly, the “laws” of thermodynamics are simply a drawing out of certain consequences of the fundamental natural laws. Biological explanations are simply high-level descriptions of what happens (in accordance with the fundamental natural laws) when physical systems happen to be organized in a particular, very complex, way. Finally, “personal” explanations are of the same type; they are high-level interpretations of how the most complex natural systems of all operate. They are a subcategory of explanations of events in terms of the fundamental laws of nature, not an entirely separate, independent type of explanation. Quote:
Quote:
Entities with the attributes of “personhood” – i.e., with desires, intentions, purposes, etc., (like saber-toothed tigers) tend to be far more dangerous than other entities. As a result, if we incorrectly identify an entity as a “non-person” (in this sense) the result could be immediate death, whereas the result of attributing these properties to things that don’t have them (such as dolls or storms) is relatively benign. So natural selection has “programmed” us to have a very strong tendency to perceive things as “persons” (at least initially) whenever there is any room for doubt. Also, there is a potential for benefiting enormously by constructive interactions with “persons” – far more so than with most other entities. And there are quite a few “persons” in our natural environment. Thus “personal” explanations tend to play a very large role in our thinking; a very large proportion of the events we experience require this kind of interpretation. So we tend to think of this category as very “fundamental”. And it is – but only in the sense that it’s fundamental to our survival and well-being, and therefore it looms large in the conceptual framework that we develop to interpret reality and predict future events – i.e., our ontology. But since it seems (and is) so “fundamental” to us in this sense, it’s all too easy to slip into the fallacy of thinking of this category as “fundamental” in a very different sense of being a basic or fundamental category of reality itself. One of the hallmarks of maturity is the recognition that we are instinctively overly inclined to attribute “personal” qualities to entities. A rational person learns to recognize this tendency and compensate for it by not promiscuously attributing “personhood” to all sorts of entities. We learn that only a very limited class of entities with certain well-defined characteristics ever have this property, and to avoid attributing it to entities that don’t meet these criteria. To attribute all of reality to a personal being is to discard everything that we learn as we mature and develop a more sophisticated understanding of the nature of things and revert to a childlike mode of thought. Quote:
Anyway, I’m not inclined to argue about whether, if we assume that there is a “person” which is the ‘ground of all being”, it is more rational to assume that it is literally omnipotent, omniscient, etc. We have at any rate to assume that it is incredibly powerful, knowledgeable, etc. Any entity capable of creating the universe and being able to know the future, etc., would have to be unimaginably far outside of all human experience. That’s enough for my argument. Quote:
But in any case, the fact that a large number of people have an “intuition” about what reality is “like” in very basic ways simply has no evidential value. Almost everyone has an intuition that time and space are two completely different things; that the question whether one event came before or after another has an objectively correct answer, that space is Euclidean, that matter and energy are two completely different things, that nothing can be in two places at the same time, that local realism holds, etc. Science is a very humbling thing: it teaches us that our fundamental intuitions, no matter how strong, no matter how certain we are of them, just cannot be trusted. |
|||||||||
02-03-2003, 07:30 PM | #135 |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Jun 2001
Location: secularcafe.org
Posts: 9,525
|
Thus I refute Kenny. |
02-04-2003, 10:33 AM | #136 | ||||||||||||||||||||
Senior Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: South Bend IN
Posts: 564
|
Like I said, I do not really wish to get side tracked on this matter, so this will be my final thread on this subject.
To restate my basic argument in another and more careful way: Metaphysical naturalism is very difficult to define, but I think perhaps it is approximately equal to the idea that the universe is explicable solely in terms of an impersonal set of physical laws. It is important to keep in mind that this is a metaphysical doctrine and not a scientific one. We are not setting science against some other hypothesis when we speak of setting theism against metaphysical naturalism, but we are setting two equally non-scientific (or, if you prefer, pre-scientific) metaphysical theories against one another. Now, the relevant question here for the metaphysical naturalist is: “If all is to be explained in terms of a set of impersonal physical laws, what are the ontological and epistemological statuses of such laws?” With respect to the ontological status of these laws, there are three possibilities: 1.) These laws instantiate solely as brute facts. 2.) These laws are ultimately instantiated by something else. 3.) These laws are somehow self-instantiating. These three ontological possibilities tie into three epistemological possibilities. 1.) If these laws instantiate as brute facts, they have no explanation. 2.) If these laws were ultimately instantiated by something else, then they are explained in terms of something else. 3.) If these laws are self-instantiating, they are in some sense self-explaining. Of theses three possibilities, number one might be said to be highly parsimonious in terms of ontology, but the purpose of maintaining ontological parsimony is to come up with the simplest explanation not to give up on explanation, so number one is not so desirable. Number two violates the assumption that Metaphysical Natualism begins with. That leaves us with number three. But, what does number three mean? Well, the only way I can think to understand the concept of being “self-instantiating” or “self-explaining” is if these laws are somehow logically necessary. If that is the case, then there must be a successful ontological argument that results in the conclusion that this set of laws exists necessarily. In the broadest possible outlines, this argument would have to look something like this: P1.) There is a conceivable set of physical laws such that if these laws are instantiated in at least one logically possible world, they instantiate in all possible worlds. P2.) This set of laws is instantiated in at least one possible world. C1.) This set of laws is instantiated in all possible worlds. Now, substitute ‘conceivable maximally perfect being’ for ‘set of physical laws’ and the above argument turns into: P1.) There is a conceivable maximally perfect being such that if this being is instantiated in at least one logically possible world, it instantiates in all possible worlds. P2.) This being is instantiated in at least one possible world. C1.) This being is instantiated in all possible worlds. Of course, the above argument, in broad outline, is the contemporary modal version of the ontological argument for the existence of God. Let’s call the first of the above ontological arguments NOA (for naturalist ontological argument) and lets call the second TOA (for theist ontological argument). Every premise of NOA maps one to one to a premise of TOA. Furthermore, every ontological or epistemological assumption in NOA also maps one to one to an epistemological or ontological assumption in TOA. In other words, neither of these two arguments can outdo the other in terms of ontological or epistemological assumptions. It follows that neither theism nor naturalism has the upper hand in terms of epistemological or ontological parsimony. Now you might protest that the contents of ‘conceivable maximally perfect being’ are vague because we do not know what ‘maximally perfect’ entails, but such is no less vague than ‘conceivable set of physical laws’ since we do not know what such a set would entail. The laws of physics as we know and understand them certainly do not look self-explaining in the way that the physical laws of the NOA would be. At best, the physical laws that we are currently aware of are a subset of the physical laws referred to in the NOA, with the content of this larger set being unknown. Now, for a few comments on your post. I’m just going to hit what I see as the highlights since your post is long and we are already off topic. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
That’s simply false. The term ‘complexity’ is an ambiguous one (and if you don’t agree, try banging your head against the wall by arguing with a young earth creationist who thinks that the second law of thermodynamics contradicts the theory of evolution), but I think the best way to understand complexity for the purposes of this debate is in terms of being described by a large number of independent predicates. The ontological argument suggests to us, however, that God’s existence can be understood in terms of a single predicate – namely ‘maximal greatness,’ ‘unlimitedness,’ or ‘maximal perfection’ – thus making God less complex than any other known being. Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
Quote:
That all being said, I’m done with debating this issue for now given that it is off topic and the main debate is already complicated. If you have any further replies in this respect, however, I will gladly read them. God Bless, Kenny |
||||||||||||||||||||
02-04-2003, 10:36 AM | #137 | |
Senior Member
Join Date: Jul 2000
Location: South Bend IN
Posts: 564
|
Quote:
God Bless, Kenny |
|
02-04-2003, 11:02 AM | #138 | |
Junior Member
Join Date: Jan 2003
Location: South Bend, IN
Posts: 47
|
Quote:
I think you've provided a very useful explanation of the MN position and its implications. Well done. K |
|
02-04-2003, 11:20 AM | #139 | |||
Junior Member
Join Date: Jan 2003
Location: South Bend, IN
Posts: 47
|
Quote:
If the claim is "there's insufficient evidence to justify theism", then that appears to assume there's some notion of what would be sufficient. Thus, I think it's reasonable to ask, what evidence for theism would you take as being sufficient. Put another way, what evidence would cause you to move from atheism to theism? Quote:
Quote:
One further comment, there seems to be some confusion regarding the question being dealt with on this thread. The question is "does theistic believe require evidence to be rational'? That doesn't mean that one who holds theistic belief without evidence has given some sort of proof or argument that God exists. The only issue is whether or not that individual is rational to do so. My argument is, yes. In this respect, I agree with Plantinga's project in his "Warrented Christian Belief". But even he points out that his argument isn't intended to prove God exists. Rather, it is intended to say that belief in God doesn't require evidence to be rational. Plantinga's challenge is to the evidentialist's claim that only those beliefs that have "sufficient evidence" can be rational. In a nutshell, the response is that the belief that that requirement is necessary is itself lacking sufficient evidence, so is self-refuting. It took Plantinga 500+ pages to get there, but that is, I think, the essence of his argument. But on its own, it isn't meant as an argument to demonstrate that God exists. K |
|||
02-04-2003, 04:56 PM | #140 | |
Veteran Member
Join Date: Aug 2002
Location: Chicago
Posts: 1,485
|
Kuyper:
Quote:
These are all extraordinary claims requiring extraordinary evidence. Your claim is even more extraordinary. Why should it be held to any lesser standard of evidence? |
|
Thread Tools | Search this Thread |
|