FRDB Archives

Freethought & Rationalism Archive

The archives are read only.


Go Back   FRDB Archives > Archives > Existence of God(s)
Welcome, Peter Kirby.
You last visited: Yesterday at 03:12 PM

 
 
Thread Tools Search this Thread
Old 09-10-2008, 10:04 AM   #111
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2003
Location: Toronto
Posts: 3,450
Default

Quote:
Originally Posted by Elfman View Post
Most slavery in that day was more similar to indentured servitude. People would place themselves as a slave to another in order to pay off debts, have provisions made for them, etc... It was more akin to the type of bargining arrangements you would find mutually satisfying for both parties.
That is the reply given by Christians so often in trying to defend the bible/slavery issue...and it is disingenuous.

You really have to do some reading as to what the life of most slaves was like throughout history, including the time of the bible. Slavery typically meant you were captured, often after war, and most slaves were treated inhumanely and viewed of course as the property of the slave owner.
Even in Rome, often pointed to as having one of the more "enlightened" systems of slavery, this was true. And even a freed slave did not have the rights of a Roman citizen.

It is undeniable that when you look at slavery in the ancient world that good, civilised people would condemn the practice and not allow it in society.

And your very holy book undermines this pretty-faced version of ancient slavery you want to present.

Quote:
Originally Posted by Elfman View Post
An honest reading of Deut. and Exodus on the passages about how to treat slaves would make that quite clear.
Riiiight.

You feel the bible has en enlightened view of how to treat one another? Yet...you know darned well you would not treat another person the way the bible condones treating slaves.

Tell me, do you think it's ok to hold people as property and to force circumcision on them? (Exodus)

Exodus Chapter 21 CLEARLY depicts and condones behaviour from a slave owner that a civilized person like yourself would NOT view as a good way to treat another human being. It says things like:

"Now these are the ordinances which you shall set before them. When you buy a Hebrew slave, he shall serve six years, and in the seventh he shall go out free, for nothing. If he comes in single, he shall go out single; if he comes in married, then his wife shall go out with him. If his master gives him a wife and she bears him sons or daughters, the wife and her children shall be her master’s and he shall go out alone. But if the slave plainly says, ‘I love my master, my wife, and my children; I will not go out free,’ then his master shall bring him to God, and he shall bring him to the door or the doorpost; and his master shall bore his ear through with an awl; and he shall serve him for life."

Right there you have God condoning BUYING another human being and that in BUYING that human being will mean he has to serve you for six years at least. There is NOTHING like the contractual, equality that you would like to imply about slavery in there.

And the very issue of this passage, the conditions under which a slave is to be set "Free," is enough to undermine the ethics. Until six years the slave is NOT FREE...not free to leave...these are the conditions that a slave must serve BEFORE HE MAY BE FREE. I don't know about you, but I value the freedom to do as I wish, work for whomever I want, rather than be the chattel property of some slave owner.

And the passage depicts someone in a position over another person such that the Slave Owner can "give" a slave a wife (or not). Hardly consonant with what you and I would consider proper: don't you feel someone should be free to fall in love with and marry who they choose, and not be under the reign of a an owner who decides whether or not to "give" you a wife or not?

Further, it depicts the poor slaves wife and children as automatically BEING THE PROPERTY OF THE SLAVE OWNER. And that the husband can go free BUT NOT THE WIFE AND KIDS because they are the slave owners property: only the original slave can go after six years!

Now point me anywhere in society that you would actually condone that. You know it goes against any enlightened view of human interaction.

Oh, and since his wife and kids are the slave owners property, if the poor slave loves his kids and family so much he can't leave them (and the slave owner isn't letting them go!) he has to pledge allegiance to his master and serve him FOR LIFE. And the slave owner marks him as his property by boring a whole through his slaves ear!

And do you think THIS is an appropriate, moral way for one human to treat another?

We both know you would condemn anyone treating other people this way.
Yet you want to portray the slavery in the bible - PRACTICES CONDONED BY THE GOD OF THE BIBLE - as not so bad. (Actually, if God condones these practices they would have to be "good" by your lights).



Quote:
Originally Posted by Elfman View Post

And even the passage you speak about says that if you beat a slave unto death than there is a penalty....that they do not die for a few days is to indicate that they probably do not die from that particular beating.
And...so....?

You have been trying to soft-peddle the bible's view of slavery. As if the slavery it depicts - the treatment of slaves CONDONED BY GOD - isn't something morally condemnable.

And yet you can't get away from the passages that starkly portray otherwise.

"If a man beats his male or female slave with a rod and the slave dies as a direct result, he must be punished, 21 but he is not to be punished if the slave gets up after a day or two, since the slave is his property. "

Yeah, sure, slavery wasn't too bad. Yet God said you can beat your slaves...in fact BEAT THEM TO ALMOST TO DEATH...so long as the slave lingeres alive and can get up after a couple of days. Why? Well, after all it's because, as God says, the slave is the owners property!

As a Christian you may have your cognitive strategies for looking away from, ignoring or rationalizing away the immorality in the bible...so you can cling to the belief it is a Good Book from a Good God. But you can't force others to ignore the text: You simply can not pull the wool over anyone's eyes about the immorality of slavery in the bible, and the immorality of what the God of the bible explicitly condones.


Quote:
Originally Posted by Elfman View Post
Why are God's desires not important in your equation? If we thwart His desires, does that not matter?
If Desire Utilitarianism is correct then God's desires DO matter, just as much...BUT NO MORE...than ours.

Prof.
Prof is offline  
Old 09-10-2008, 11:34 AM   #112
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2003
Location: Toronto
Posts: 3,450
Default

Hi Antiplastic. Great questions as always. I only have so much time and this
portion seems to contain the crux of the issue:

Quote:
Originally Posted by Antiplastic View Post

Too quick. Hypothetical imperatives are widely known to be translatable into fact statements. I don't know anyone who has ever denied this. But you keep hopping back and forth between noncontroversial statements about hypothetical oughts to categorical oughts, and since Elfman sees it and I see it it's strange why you can't see it too.
And:

Quote:
Originally Posted by Antiplastic View Post

If you freeze this passage and watch it in slow motion, you can see where the equivocation takes place.

Pretty much any desire in practical reason pertains to other desires, since humans are constantly in a state of dynamic tension wrt their subjective desire sets. We are always revising, resolving, shuffling, accommodating, struggling to reorder our psychic priorities and to drag our behavior in line with them. Of course the question of whether I should have a drink "pertains to other desires". I try to quash it when I've got work to do, and I indulge it when I'm celebrating with friends; in either case, I'm juggling it with all my other conflicting and supporting desires. (And this is just on the conscious level! It's not like there is some finite "list of desires" a person has that they could just write down if they had a big enough spreadsheet; there's also untold subconscious desires most of us go our entire lives without even being aware of.)

But the real switch comes when you go from the noncontroversial "maximizing my own subjective desire set" to the highly controversial "maximizing anyone's desires other than my own". On your own terms, there is no reason to do so absent an antecedent desire to do so. And that is precisely the point at issue.
First I want to point out that the very fact you agree with the general assessment of what some call "Hypothetical imperatives" - an example being the vacation in Spain - is one reason I actually find the Desire Utilitarian system more compelling. (I don't want to get into an argument splitting hairs over Kant's notion of Hypothetical Imperatives vs ones I might tweak...so I'll stick to that nomenclenture for now).

The very fact that the reasoning underlying hypothetical imperatives ("Practical oughts") is in the main uncontroversial seems to me significant. Because the direct relationship of a desire in making sense of the ought statement, the way a desire is necessary for providing the reasons for action, seems to me to underline the link between desire and "ought" statements.

The problem I find when I read most ethical theories is that many will condone this link for "Hypothetical imperatives," but then suddenly say "But of course that doesn't mean moral oughts have any such necessary link." And then they jettison the link of desires to "ought" and flail about trying to find SOME grounding for moral oughts somewhere else. And I find this is always that breakdown, when the moral theorist looses his footing and he seems to struggle.

Ought questions amount to questions of "What should I do?" They are by nature looking for reasons for action. This is the case whether we talk of "ought I buy X pair of running shoes" to "ought I steal that car or respect it as the owner's property?"

To me it makes senses that if a desire is necessary to makes sense of an ought when we are speaking of practical desires...why in the world would we presume this link, this logical underpinning, would suddenly vanish when it comes to any other "ought?"

It does not make sense to me that it would. And the very flailing about within moral philosophy (very sophisticated flailing, mind you) to find a ground for moral "oughts" seems to me to underline this insight.

So if we start with the soundness of "Hypothetical imperatives," in this case that "ought" is a question about reasons for actions, and those reasons only make sense in appeal to a desire, then there seems nothing logically stopping this trend to extending to any ought, including moral "oughts" which ask for reasons for action.

Now to the excellent question of making that step from "personal, "Hypothetical/practical imperatives "oughts" to how we "ought" to treat other people:

The answer, I would posit, combines what I'd already written in response to Elfman earlier: the nature of REASON. Since ought statements are asking about reasons-for-action, we are obviously looking to reason to answer the questions. And to use reason is to apply principles - principles that are hardy and "work" in answering similar questions in other possible circumstances. Hence reason, in it's appeal to principles, entails a universality. If you are being reasonable, you aren't just pulling premises out of your ass that only happen to apply to one particular possible case.

This is why, as I pointed out to Elfman, it is so difficult to actually JUSTIFY via REASON a system of pure selfishness. Every time you try you essentially, by the universality of principles, justify other people acting the same way. Even if you wanted to steal, you could not justify it logically without condoning it, logically, for others to steal from you. But you actually wouldn't think it IS the case other people ought to steal your stuff...the the
attempt at justification for your stealing breaks down. (So long as it's a purely selfish justification). You can certainly still steal for selfish reasons, but you can't justify it as the most reasonable attitude, for this reason.

So, back to DU. As Alonzo Fyfe puts it: " Desire utilitarianism not only compares states of affairs to desires (to see if the state of affairs would fulfill or thwart those desires), it looks at the desires themselves to determine if people generally have reason to inhibit or promote those desires."

It is generally uncontroversial in moral theory that "ought" implies "can."
So far as you can do something, so far as there is some choice, the question of "ought" can pertain.

And desires are not immutable. They can be influenced (the examples are so obvious and numerous I figure I don't have to even lay out all the examples). Hence it's possible to encourage one desire over another. And this possibility naturally brings with it "ought." The question can be asked "Ought one have X desire or not?" (Or "Ought X desire be encouraged, or discouraged").

We've seen that a DESIRE is necessary to make sense of the ought in previous "oughts" (hypothetical).
Only in the presence of, and relation to, a DESIRE do reasons-for-actions occur. (If there existed no desires...there would exist no reasons to do anything). If it is the case that we can't make sense of "ought" without a desire in other areas...I see no
reason why this necessary connection would vanish when asking another "ought" question - any ought question.

So in asking "ought I have X desire" I am asking "do I have reasons to hold or discourage having this desire?" Since desires provide the reasons for actions we must appeal to other desires: Does X desire fulfill other desires?
If it does, then it's a desire you ought to have. Your other desires provide REASONS for holding desire X.

How does this universalize beyond mere personal concerns, in the way morality is supposed to universalize? Again, that's where the universalizing nature of reason comes in.

The problem is that, once OTHER desires are introduced into the equation - when you interact with the desires of other people - universalizing selfish desires fails. It becomes virtually self-refuting.

Morality pertains when we must answer how to treat other beings with desires.

Say say you are asking "Ought I steal?" That is asking for reasons-for-actions (reasons to steal). You could say that the desire to steal my stuff is particularly strong. Doesn't that mean you "ought" to steal my stuff?
Well, if you say "Because I desire to steal your stuff, I ought to steal your stuff" that
automatically condones me stealing your stuff for the same reason. You've endorsed that reasoning principle: the presence of a desire to steal is reason to steal.

But, actually, you WOULDN'T condone my stealing your stuff. Even if I DESIRE to steal your stuff, you don't want me to steal it. You DESIRE to keep your own stuff and not have it stolen, so you don't endorse the principle you thought you would - at least not without the consequences of having your own desires thwarted by me. So it's self-defeating: the principle does not hold, because your own desire to keep your stuff refutes it and makes nonsense of the principle.

You are asking "ought I have the desire to steal," and you are failing to produce a GOOD REASON to steal, because the you would not actually endorse the universalization of that reasoning (and the very act of reasoning
that you ought to steal because you desire to do so DOES by necessity have to apply universally, if you are reasoning soundly).

So you have REASONS to discourage the desire to steal, both in yourself and in your neighbour, because the desire to steal has the tendency to thwart desires - yours and your neighbours. Instead it could be replaced by a desire - e.g. the desire to respect one another's property - that does not have the tendency of thwarting desires when universalized. In fact, cooperative/respectful desires have the tendency of FULFILLING more, other desires. Hence you have REASONS to promote the desire for cooperation/respect and REASONS to discourage the desire to steal.

To put things as clearly as I can manage:

There is no fundamental difference in making sense of "ought" questions: all ought questions appeal to desires (and states of affairs that would fulfill those desires) to answer whether one "ought" to do something.

Moral "oughts" are no different in this underlying logic - they are of the same fundamental nature as "hypothetical imperatives"
insofar as they must appeal to desires for justification. The only difference is in their categorization. Generally: moral "desires" are the category of desires we have reasons to promote universally - as opposed to those desires, for instance my desire to eat chilli-dogs, which are hypothetical/practical oughts that we do not have reasons to promote universally.

So the answer to any "ought" question is "does it fulfill the desire in question?"

If you asked: "Ought I use X saw to cut you up?" I'd say: "The answer depends on the desire in question?" Are you looking for the answer relative to a practical/hypothetical "ought" question, or a moral ought question?

If the desire in question was your personal, selfish desire to cut someone up with a saw, the answer would be "yes": if it were true that X saw were "such as to fulfill the desire in question" then it's the case "you ought to select saw X for the job."

But if the desire in question had to do with a desire that falls into the moral category: "Would it be moral to cut you up with this saw?" Or "Do we have reasons to promote the desire for cutting other people up with saws?"
Then the answer would be "No. It would not be moral to do so. We have reasons to discourage that desire, not promote it."

Hence cutting up someone with a saw would not fulfill the desire-to-act-morally. It is immoral (which equates to: a desire that has the tendency of thwarting desires, esp when universalized, hence we have reasons to discourage such desires).

Whew...

That was all typed pretty fast. My apologies if I haven't been clear somewhere. I look forward to any criticisms should they be forthcoming.

Cheers,

Prof.
Prof is offline  
Old 09-10-2008, 02:05 PM   #113
Veteran
 
Join Date: May 2007
Location: Adrift on Neurath's Raft
Posts: 1,787
Default

Quote:
Originally Posted by Prof View Post

Quote:
Originally Posted by Antiplastic View Post

Too quick. Hypothetical imperatives are widely known to be translatable into fact statements. I don't know anyone who has ever denied this. But you keep hopping back and forth between noncontroversial statements about hypothetical oughts to categorical oughts, and since Elfman sees it and I see it it's strange why you can't see it too.
And:

Quote:
Originally Posted by Antiplastic View Post

If you freeze this passage and watch it in slow motion, you can see where the equivocation takes place.

Pretty much any desire in practical reason pertains to other desires, since humans are constantly in a state of dynamic tension wrt their subjective desire sets. We are always revising, resolving, shuffling, accommodating, struggling to reorder our psychic priorities and to drag our behavior in line with them. Of course the question of whether I should have a drink "pertains to other desires". I try to quash it when I've got work to do, and I indulge it when I'm celebrating with friends; in either case, I'm juggling it with all my other conflicting and supporting desires. (And this is just on the conscious level! It's not like there is some finite "list of desires" a person has that they could just write down if they had a big enough spreadsheet; there's also untold subconscious desires most of us go our entire lives without even being aware of.)

But the real switch comes when you go from the noncontroversial "maximizing my own subjective desire set" to the highly controversial "maximizing anyone's desires other than my own". On your own terms, there is no reason to do so absent an antecedent desire to do so. And that is precisely the point at issue.
First I want to point out that the very fact you agree with the general assessment of what some call "Hypothetical imperatives" - an example being the vacation in Spain - is one reason I actually find the Desire Utilitarian system more compelling.
I don’t understand what’s “compelling” about it. As I said, I’m not aware of a single philosopher, ancient or modern, who has ever denied anything either of us have said about practical reasoning. It’s really just common pre-theoretical concepts and vocabulary.

Quote:
The very fact that the reasoning underlying hypothetical imperatives ("Practical oughts") is in the main uncontroversial seems to me significant. Because the direct relationship of a desire in making sense of the ought statement, the way a desire is necessary for providing the reasons for action, seems to me to underline the link between desire and "ought" statements.

The problem I find when I read most ethical theories is that many will condone this link for "Hypothetical imperatives," but then suddenly say "But of course that doesn't mean moral oughts have any such necessary link." And then they jettison the link of desires to "ought" and flail about trying to find SOME grounding for moral oughts somewhere else. And I find this is always that breakdown, when the moral theorist looses his footing and he seems to struggle.
If by “they jettison the link of desires to oughts” you mean they try to talk about moral truths without any reference to real human hopes and human aspirations, then of course this is doomed to fail. However it’s important not to beg the question against antirealism by pounding the table and insisting, “but there must be a ground for moral claims!”

But if by “they jettison the link of desires to oughts” you mean they try to provide reasons to act morally irrespective of a given agent’s subjective desire set, this just is the problem of moral objectivity, going back to the Parable of the Ring of Gyges. Since (as I maintain) you are equivocal on this issue, this sometimes seems like something you claim to have succeeded in doing, to the extent you seem to claim a reason to act in such a way as to thwart most or all of one’s own desires.

So could you clear this up? Does it or does it not make sense to say that some agent A could have a reason – a practical, ordinary, noncontroversial hypothetical imperative -- to act against the maximization of his own subjective desire set?

(If it helps to alleviate the feeling of shadowboxing, I can give you a target. My own answer is that it is contradictory on its face to say that someone has a rational obligation – an obligation in practical reason – to act against his own happiness. But I think that moral discourse is a separate language game which does not require the truth of any particular hypothetical imperative to function, and in fact does not require any sort of “grounding” at all.)

Quote:
Ought questions amount to questions of "What should I do?" They are by nature looking for reasons for action. This is the case whether we talk of "ought I buy X pair of running shoes" to "ought I steal that car or respect it as the owner's property?"

To me it makes senses that if a desire is necessary to makes sense of an ought when we are speaking of practical desires...why in the world would we presume this link, this logical underpinning, would suddenly vanish when it comes to any other "ought?"

It does not make sense to me that it would. And the very flailing about within moral philosophy (very sophisticated flailing, mind you) to find a ground for moral "oughts" seems to me to underline this insight.
To reiterate, you can’t just beg the question by assuming, against the antirealists, that moral oughts can be “made sense of” or “grounded” through some metaphysical inquiry.

Quote:
So if we start with the soundness of "Hypothetical imperatives," in this case that "ought" is a question about reasons for actions, and those reasons only make sense in appeal to a desire, then there seems nothing logically stopping this trend to extending to any ought, including moral "oughts" which ask for reasons for action.
The logical gap is relatively straightforward: moral practice routinely, as a commonplace, puts demands on our behavior which run contrary to our subjective desire sets. Either the practice is wrong (or illusory), or the philosophical justification in terms of a reduction to hypothetical imperatives is wrong.

Quote:
Now to the excellent question of making that step from "personal, "Hypothetical/practical imperatives "oughts" to how we "ought" to treat other people:

The answer, I would posit, combines what I'd already written in response to Elfman earlier: the nature of REASON. Since ought statements are asking about reasons-for-action, we are obviously looking to reason to answer the questions. And to use reason is to apply principles - principles that are hardy and "work" in answering similar questions in other possible circumstances. Hence reason, in it's appeal to principles, entails a universality. If you are being reasonable, you aren't just pulling premises out of your ass that only happen to apply to one particular possible case.

This is why, as I pointed out to Elfman, it is so difficult to actually JUSTIFY via REASON a system of pure selfishness. Every time you try you essentially, by the universality of principles, justify other people acting the same way. Even if you wanted to steal, you could not justify it logically without condoning it, logically, for others to steal from you. But you actually wouldn't think it IS the case other people ought to steal your stuff...the the attempt at justification for your stealing breaks down. (So long as it's a purely selfish justification). You can certainly still steal for selfish reasons, but you can't justify it as the most reasonable attitude, for this reason.
Sorry, but this is still where the equivocation comes in. You might not be able to justify to other people why you’re doing what you do, but it doesn’t follow that your behavior is irrational, or that you have any false beliefs about the universe. Because, on your own terms, it is perfectly true and valid to say that a person ought to <paradigm example of immoral act> when it fulfills his own desires. Per your own definition, he is acting reasonably and rationally if he acts immorally.

Ought he or oughtn’t he? You get a contradiction because (as I maintain) you are equivocating between hypothetical and categorical claims.

Now, you have hit on an important point in universalizability that needs to be emphasized. I think that moral justification is a different language game from practical justification precisely because the former requires universalizability where the latter doesn’t. The fact that I don’t like someone’s behavior counts against whether I find it morally justified, but by definition it does not count against whether I find it practically justified. Therefore, the two language games are not the same.

Quote:
We've seen that a DESIRE is necessary to make sense of the ought in previous "oughts" (hypothetical).
Only in the presence of, and relation to, a DESIRE do reasons-for-actions occur. (If there existed no desires...there would exist no reasons to do anything). If it is the case that we can't make sense of "ought" without a desire in other areas...I see no reason why this necessary connection would vanish when asking another "ought" question - any ought question.
Once again, just because something is “necessary” for some project to succeed does not mean that it exists.

Quote:
So in asking "ought I have X desire" I am asking "do I have reasons to hold or discourage having this desire?" Since desires provide the reasons for actions we must appeal to other desires: Does X desire fulfill other desires? If it does, then it's a desire you ought to have. Your other desires provide REASONS for holding desire X.
Yes. Your other desires. Not anyone else’s.

Quote:
How does this universalize beyond mere personal concerns, in the way morality is supposed to universalize? Again, that's where the universalizing nature of reason comes in.

The problem is that, once OTHER desires are introduced into the equation - when you interact with the desires of other people - universalizing selfish desires fails.
See? Only two paragraphs ago you were talking about one’s own desires, but now you’re talking about other people’s desires. I continue to insist you’re equivocating.

Quote:
Morality pertains when we must answer how to treat other beings with desires.

Say say you are asking "Ought I steal?" That is asking for reasons-for-actions (reasons to steal). You could say that the desire to steal my stuff is particularly strong. Doesn't that mean you "ought" to steal my stuff?
Well, if you say "Because I desire to steal your stuff, I ought to steal your stuff" that
automatically condones me stealing your stuff for the same reason. You've endorsed that reasoning principle: the presence of a desire to steal is reason to steal.
But by definition you agree that the presence of a desire to steal is a necessary and sufficient condition for there to be a (defeasible) reason to steal!

Quote:
But, actually, you WOULDN'T condone my stealing your stuff. Even if I DESIRE to steal your stuff, you don't want me to steal it. You DESIRE to keep your own stuff and not have it stolen, so you don't endorse the principle you thought you would - at least not without the consequences of having your own desires thwarted by me. So it's self-defeating: the principle does not hold, because your own desire to keep your stuff refutes it and makes nonsense of the principle.
I don’t want you to steal my stuff. But by definition, I cannot convict you of an error in practical reasoning if you do.

Quote:
You are asking "ought I have the desire to steal," and you are failing to produce a GOOD REASON to steal, because the you would not actually endorse the universalization of that reasoning (and the very act of reasoning that you ought to steal because you desire to do so DOES by necessity have to apply universally, if you are reasoning soundly).

So you have REASONS to discourage the desire to steal, both in yourself and in your neighbour, because the desire to steal has the tendency to thwart desires - yours and your neighbours.
Correction: I have reasons to discourage everyone else from stealing.

Quote:
Instead it could be replaced by a desire - e.g. the desire to respect one another's property - that does not have the tendency of thwarting desires when universalized. In fact, cooperative/respectful desires have the tendency of FULFILLING more, other desires. Hence you have REASONS to promote the desire for cooperation/respect and REASONS to discourage the desire to steal.

To put things as clearly as I can manage:

There is no fundamental difference in making sense of "ought" questions: all ought questions appeal to desires (and states of affairs that would fulfill those desires) to answer whether one "ought" to do something.

Moral "oughts" are no different in this underlying logic - they are of the same fundamental nature as "hypothetical imperatives"
insofar as they must appeal to desires for justification. The only difference is in their categorization. Generally: moral "desires" are the category of desires we have reasons to promote universally - as opposed to those desires, for instance my desire to eat chilli-dogs, which are hypothetical/practical oughts that we do not have reasons to promote universally.
Sorry, this is a bit incoherent. “The only difference between hypothetical imperatives and categorical imperatives is that the latter are categorical”?

Quote:
So the answer to any "ought" question is "does it fulfill the desire in question?"

If you asked: "Ought I use X saw to cut you up?" I'd say: "The answer depends on the desire in question?" Are you looking for the answer relative to a practical/hypothetical "ought" question, or a moral ought question?
Again, “moral oughts give the same answers as practical oughts, except they don’t”? The answer is equivocal, because the terms are equivocal.
Antiplastic is offline  
Old 09-11-2008, 02:07 AM   #114
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jan 2005
Location: Pua, in northern Thailand
Posts: 2,823
Default

Hey Elfman, stop evading the essential point ...

God does not just allow suffering, He created it!

God created diseases and natural disasters, therefore He is a monster. You can't just keep pretending that all the bad things that happen to human beings are the result of free will.
Joan of Bark is offline  
Old 09-11-2008, 06:18 AM   #115
Regular Member
 
Join Date: Feb 2008
Location: Virginia, USA
Posts: 340
Default suffering....

Quote:
Originally Posted by Joan of Bark View Post
Hey Elfman, stop evading the essential point ...

God does not just allow suffering, He created it!

God created diseases and natural disasters, therefore He is a monster. You can't just keep pretending that all the bad things that happen to human beings are the result of free will.
I am surprised that you think suffering is morally wrong. What do you base this on? Is suffering wrong because it violates some absolute moral law that is out there? (Which would necessitate asking where such a law comes from) Or is it just wrong because you dont like it? (Which would make it an opinion based on some personal construct such as "reason.")
Elfman is offline  
Old 09-11-2008, 06:52 AM   #116
Regular Member
 
Join Date: Feb 2008
Location: Virginia, USA
Posts: 340
Default a second response....

Quote:
Originally Posted by Joan of Bark View Post
Hey Elfman, stop evading the essential point ...

God does not just allow suffering, He created it!

God created diseases and natural disasters, therefore He is a monster. You can't just keep pretending that all the bad things that happen to human beings are the result of free will.

As a second point, I realized that I did not answer your question, so I will endeavor to, though I have no illusion that you will really "get it":
The general view is that the fall of man (adam's rebellion) caused God to punish all mankind. (Which on the surface seems unfair in itself, but that is a different point to be dealt with seperately) Part of that punishment was God withdrawing himself, in part, from His creation. He no longer walks in the garden. Also, in response to Adam's rebellion, the ground was cursed and now man would have to toil to make things grow, etc... All these things were a response to man's rebellion, not an arbitrary act of God wishing to hurt people for His own sake.
Now I do not know how much of natural evil is caused directly by the curse, or how much of it was the natural byproduct of God's withdrawing, or how much of it might just be part of a larger plan. But I think that all probably play a part. As God is the sustainer of His creation, as he withdraws, things start to fall apart. So in essence, some natural evil (floods, famine, etc...) are caused merely by the fact that God is not working to sustain His creation as closely as He may have once done, but instead lets it run its own course - which, like anything else apart from God, tends to not work out so well. Now I think there is evidence, scientifically, to catastrophic global events going back a long way (such as what killed the dinosaurs), so some of these "natural evils" may have been part of a bigger plan. I put "evils" in quotes because I disagree with the tenant that all suffering is "evil." Jesus suffered on the cross to pay for my sins, that was a beautiful and necessary thing to do, and it was totally part of God's plan. ANd yet I maintain that those who tortured and killed Jesus, unjustly, are responsible for their actions. (Side note: they may not be held responsible for their actions as Jesus prayed they would be forgiven.)
So, is suffering always "evil". No. So then I am not disturbed that God uses it in His plan, or causes it in the punishment of the wicked. I don't see any reason that God must cover the earth with pillows so that no one will ever skin a knee in order for Him to be a good God....especially in light of man's rebellion. This view is founded on some "omni-love" God that isn't biblical. In order for God to be just, he must punish the wicked. That, by its nature, involves suffering.
If God doesn't exist than suffering is just put into the fatalistic "oh well, guess bad things just happen" category because it has no meaning. There can be little learned from it. Understood in context, a Christian can say "yeah it sucks because the world is broken and not as it ought to be, but better days are coming!" One view provides hope, the other despair.
Elfman is offline  
Old 09-11-2008, 07:32 AM   #117
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Aug 2006
Location: Right outside the Hub
Posts: 1,012
Default Finally a cut to the quick!

Quote:
One view provides hope, the other despair.
So you despair at the notion that bad things simply happen?

Funny, I feel the opposite way. The notion that God created us, now considers us broken and wants us to worship him until he scoops us up in the end days seems fatalistic and sad to me. Accepting the notion that bad things are caused by natural means means that we can use natural means to prevent or reverse bad things, which I find uplifting and encouraging.

Oh, and please do respond to my previous post, #103.:wave:
connick is offline  
Old 09-11-2008, 08:53 AM   #118
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Aug 2003
Location: https://soundcloud.com/dark-blue-man
Posts: 3,526
Smile

Be under no illusion, we "get it" all right :huh:

Adam and Eve (the latter created from a spare rib), a magic tree, a talking snake, a curse on the whole of mankind for disobeying a vengeful god..... sounds like another creation myth (one among many) to me. Yet here we are in 21st century and some people still think it's real. That bit we don't get........

Quote:
Imagine you’re God.

You create the universe, then Adam and Eve, and they are perfect beings. You place them in a lush garden, into which you’ve also made a special tree. The fruit of this tree, if eaten by a human, will cause them to understand “right from wrong”, and they will thus lose their perfection (why you created such a tree is unclear, but that’s another story). At some point, you also created a sneaky snake and put it proximate to your first children. Snakes, being what they are, it’s not long before Eve is duped into eating the fruit, and she then proceeds to peer pressure Adam into eating it as well.

Returning from wherever you were, you cannot find Adam and Eve straight away – after some searching, you find them hiding their naked bodies from you. This strikes you as odd because they wouldn’t be hiding if they weren’t ashamed/embarrassed – you’re on to them – they probably ate the fruit. Sure enough, after some probing, they come clean and admit their bad deed. This makes you mad, and so you curse all snakes with a belly crawling existence (which they don’t seem to mind too much – snakes do quite well as a species), you make it such that Eve, and all women hence, will experience great pain during childbirth (why you chose that punishment is not clear – how does knowing right from wrong translate to something about the 24 hours or so of labor?), and your punishment for man is that he will have to work for life’s necessities – as opposed to just sitting around in Eden.

So, many years later, the many descendants of A&E are running around acting really badly. Not believing in you, fornicating, just being jerks. This makes you really mad, and so to punish them, and set an example for future people, you drown millions of men, women, and children, and also millions of animals. You spare a few humans, and two of every kind of animal (presumably because you didn’t want to have to create them again…which you could have done).

In time, the earth repopulates itself. Humans once again act badly, but for some reason, you pay particular attention to those living in a very specific area of the globe – the middle east. Over a few centuries, you do all kinds of things like kill or have killed hundreds of thousands of people who do bad things such as not believing in you and having sex. Presumably this is to set the example of how bad it is to not believe in you, and that sex (or even thinking about it) is filthy under anything but very specific conditions.

This still doesn’t seem to work, so you finally decide to go down there yourself – but you don’t want to just poof in like a great genie (cuz if you made your existence too obvious, you’d take the faith out of faith). So, you resolve to go down as a common man. Once down there, you cruise around for a while, in your early 20’s you preach a lot, particularly about how important you are, and how important it is to believe in you. To kick up the ante a bit, let people know you are who you say you are, you perform a miracle or two – here and there. Some believe, but still others don’t. So, you head into Jerusalem and stir things up by angering the Jews and Romans – simply by claiming to be you. So they torture and “kill” you. Being unkillable, you bide your time for a few days and then reappear. This is supposed to have the effect of REALLY making people believe you are who you say you are, and that your message is Truth and Goodness. Before you leave, you tell a few people that you’ll be back again real soon – sooner than a generation or two. Since you didn’t return, you presumably did this as yet another test of humans dedication to you.

All while this is going on, the Devil is racing about tricking people into not believing in you and doing bad things. It’s not clear why you don’t put an end to the Devil, but the likely reason is that you want to see which humans are of strong enough character to not be tricked by him (which itself is puzzling because you made the humans and their character, and you presumably “know” the past, present, and future anyway).

Once back in heaven, you kick back for a while and see how the humans will take the message you gave when you came down to earth. Things start slowly, your earliest fans are fed to lions by the Romans, but your message is taken up by the poor and downtrodden, who are sick and tired of the elitist, powerful Romans. A few centuries go by, the pagan Roman destroys itself, and with a man named Constantine, your message becomes seated at the top of human power. But, people being people, there is much argument/debate over what your message really is, and how it should be applied. You watch as the drama unfolds – centuries go by and your message is taken to every corner of the earth (usually at the expense of the cultures that existed prior). Great factions with differing opinions of your message manifest themselves.

Incidentally, you never really seemed to pay much attention to people like Asians, Africans, Australians, Island peoplels, Native Americans, etc. At least not in the sense of mentioning these people in the Bible, or giving them the same set of rules as you gave Jewish people (actually, you do mention some Africans in the Bible - apparently hundreds of thousands of Ethiopians deserved to be killed because they didn't believe in you).

Anywho, the human condition will apparently go on for a while, some people will believe in you, some won’t. And one day, as you promised in the early first century, you’ll return, all evil will be destroyed, those humans who believe/believed in you will live in great everlasting peace with you, and those who didn’t, won’t (which will presumably suck bad for them).

And….sooooo….thennnn…..yeah….you did all that cuz why again? When you look back in retrospect, you kinda wonder what you were thinking?? Were you just bored? Did you make your children, the humans, for your entertainment? Why did you focus your attention so narrowly when you went down to earth? Why didn’t you spend more time down there? When you look back you think to yourself – You know, I am all about being perfect in everything, especially love. I guess it wasn’t the best decision to create these poor, helpless creatures, the humans, in such a manner that not all of them could experience my perfect love. A wise father treats ALL his children with respect and love, unconditionally, even if they don’t agree with his views – after all, it was HIS decision to bring them into the world. A wise father doesn’t disown a child who disagrees with him, or otherwise doesn’t follow his “rules”. And a wise father certainly doesn’t kill his children for doing these things.

You imagine you’d do it better next time.
A Unknown poster somewhere in net land.......
Hedshaker is offline  
Old 09-11-2008, 09:28 AM   #119
Veteran Member
 
Join Date: Jul 2003
Location: Toronto
Posts: 3,450
Default

I like this one - a nugget from a poster (on this forum?) that I saved long ago.
A lot of Christians "trust in God's plan." Yet looking at God's track record of planning, one hardly can have trust in anything The Big Guy attempts to do:


"Let's review God's track record. He creates a host of angels, and 1/3 of them rebel, including the best one of the lot. Then he makes the earth and populates it with people (well, two anyway), and calls it "good", but the next thing you know they rebel. So he tries to fix that with his Godly wisdom, but it gets to the point where he says he repents for having ever made those pesky humans, and thus drowns the lot of them, save Noah and his family that he thinks are righteous (Noah's righteousness was, of course, called into question not long after the flood). Later he selects a Chosen People, and gives them a Law, but they continuously rebel, messing up several Godly attempts he makes to set them right. So then he has to go to Plan B, er, Plan C, or is it D, E, F.....??? A new way of choosing people and setting up a Church, the body of Christ. What happens? He gets thousands of different sects, each interpreting his "plan" differently, and about half of them thinking the other half are doomed to Hell.



You think God knows what he's doing? Nothing he's recorded to have done has worked out "right" (like he planned), unless you think he planned for everything to get all screwed up over and over again, and for the majority of his human creations to end up in Hell. And with this track record you think God's promised solution is gonna work out for us, or for him, the way he's "planned" it?"




Prof.
Prof is offline  
Old 09-11-2008, 12:44 PM   #120
Regular Member
 
Join Date: Feb 2008
Location: Virginia, USA
Posts: 340
Default eurthyphro ....

Prof (and others):
I dont really agree entirely with this, but as I am still working things out in my head, I would be interested in your responses to this from William Lane Craig's website...he is answering a letter from someone working on the issue....the guys starts by mentioning that he thinks the idea of morality should be grounded in God's nature, yet he has been challenged that this merely brings up the question as to why God's nature is good. So he comes up with this:

"
(1) God is, by definition, a maximally great being.
(2) This entails His being metaphysically necessary and morally perfect.
(3) Therefore, by (2), God exists in all possible worlds.
(4) But, if moral values are objective, moral perfection represents (or
at least tends towards) a unique, maximal set of moral values.
(5) So, by (1), (3) & (4), it follows that God has the same moral
character in every possible world.
(6) Therefore God’s nature is good neither because of the way He
happens to be nor because of His fitness with reference to an external
standard of goodness.
—which answers the reformulated dilemma.

James



Dr. Craig responds:

I think your intuitions are right on target, James! The argument you give just needs some adjustment.

When the atheist says, “Is God’s nature good because of the way God happens to be, or is it good because it matches up to some external standard of goodness?”, the second horn of the dilemma represents nothing new—it’s the same as the second horn in the original dilemma, namely, that God approves something because it’s good, and we’ve already rejected that. So the question is whether we’re stuck on the first horn of the dilemma. Well, if by “happens to be” the atheist means that God’s moral character is a contingent property of God, that is to say, a property God could have lacked, then the obvious answer is, “No.” God’s moral character is essential to Him; that’s why we said it was part of His nature. To say that some property is essential to God is to say that there is no possible world in which God could have existed and lacked that property. God didn’t just happen by accident to be loving, kind, just, and so forth. He is that way essentially.

You needn’t worry about “what it means to say this, since unless we have a concept of the Good outside of God, this doesn’t seem to amount to much.” For this is to confuse moral ontology with moral semantics. Our concern is with moral ontology, that is to say, the foundation in reality of moral values. Our concern is not with moral semantics, that is to say, the meaning of moral terms. The theist is quite ready to say that we have a clear understanding of moral vocabulary like “good,” “evil,” right,” and so on, without reference to God. Thus, it is informative to learn that “God is essentially good.” Too often opponents of the moral argument launch misguided attacks upon it by confusing moral ontology with either moral semantics or, even more often, moral epistemology (how we come to know the Good).

If it be asked why God is the paradigm and standard of moral goodness, then I think premise (1) of your argument gives the answer: God is the greatest conceivable being, and it is greater to be the paradigm of goodness than to conform to it. Your premise (2) is also true, which is why God can serve as the foundation of necessary moral truths, i.e., moral truths which hold in every possible world. I’m not sure what you mean by premise (4); but I think it’s dispensable. All you need to say is that moral values (or at least many of them) are not contingent, but hold in every possible world. Then God will ground these values in every possible world. That seems to me to settle the issue. "


Thanks
Elfman is offline  
 

Thread Tools Search this Thread
Search this Thread:

Advanced Search

Forum Jump


All times are GMT -8. The time now is 08:38 PM.

Top

This custom BB emulates vBulletin® Version 3.8.2
Copyright ©2000 - 2015, Jelsoft Enterprises Ltd.